Sandridge, Norman B. 2012. Loving Humanity, Learning, and Being Honored: The Foundations of Leadership in Xenophon's Education of Cyrus. Hellenic Studies Series 55. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_SandridgeN.Loving_Humanity_Learning_and_Being_Honored.2012.
Chapter 2. Curiosity, Aptitude, and Intense Awareness
The first thing to note about Cyrus’ philomatheia is that it seems to be a natural curiosity. I say, “natural,” because Xenophon does not attribute Cyrus’ inquisitiveness to any encouragement he receives from others, nor does it seem to be influenced by particular interests. The young Cyrus is merely interested in having the causes of things explained to him. To this extent he is like Plato’s Philosopher King, who is both a philomathês and a lover of wisdom (philosophos). {45|46} This is the only instance, however, where Cyrus’ curiosity is portrayed as open-ended, without any ulterior motive or particular field.
This is the final of the four uses of the philomath– stem in Xenophon, and it again seems to have application to a specific field. Xenophon does not treat all forms of the “love of learning” as pleasurable in themselves, though certain subjects may be so. In this respect Xenophon disagrees with Plato’s Socrates, who says that a lover of something must be a lover of all aspects of something, whether the person in question is a lover of a person or a lover of honor (Republic 474c–475e). As lovers of learning, both of Xenophon’s Cyruses seem to love learning specific subjects more than the learning itself. {48|49}
Socrates himself regards pleasure in learning a subject (farming) as the basis of philosophy:
From the foregoing examples, it would seem that Xenophon’s understanding of the love of learning is not generally open-ended; only in limited ways does it seem to be learning for its own sake. We might say, for example, that Cyrus loves learning to hunt as an end in itself (since he pursues it so monomaniacally) but also as a means of winning honor, as evidenced by the fact that he is eager to share the spoils of the hunt with his grandfather and friends.
Aptitude for Learning
Paying Attention
The tradition of the “wakeful leader” in Greek literature goes back to Homer’s Iliad, where Cambyses’ sentiment is first articulated by Dream, who stresses the importance of paying attention to the sleeping Agamemnon:
Cyrus follows Cambyses’ advice throughout his campaign. Xenophon portrays him as continually restless in monitoring his army: “he himself in fact did not occupy one place but he rode around, now here, now there, looking out and paying attention to see if the army needed anything.” [14] Even in his youth, Cyrus shows this inquisitiveness and wakefulness. As soon as Cyrus learns of the encroachment that the Assyrians have made on Medan territory, he dons his armor and joins his grandfather, to his astonishment (1.4.18). Once Cyrus takes a survey of the situation, he poses a series of questions and then advocates making a charge upon the enemy, at first against Astyages’ better judgment (note again Cyrus’ “kingly” daring). He eventually prevails upon his grandfather who again marvels at Cyrus’ “sensibility and wakefulness” (cf. καὶ ἐφρόνει καὶ ἐγρηγόρει, 1.4.20.2). Later among his Persian contemporaries the young Cyrus wins a reputation for outstanding diligence toward his lessons (1.5.1). The payoff of attentiveness is more than mental: on the eve of their first battle with the Assyrians, Cyrus inspires his men with the assurance that he has been “observing” their valor since childhood (1.5.7). {53|54}
By showing that he observes all of his followers’ behavior, Cyrus instills an intense philotîmia in them. Because of their constant practice, they together perform every kind of noble deed (8.1.39). Because of his great memory, Cyrus learns the names of his followers and oversees the selection of his closest associates. [15] Xenophon says that Cyrus saw good leaders as “a law with eyes,” not only able to give instruction like the written law but also able to observe transgressors and punish them. [16]
Conclusion
Footnotes