Who Am I? (Mis)Identity and the Polis in Oedipus Tyrannus

  Karakantza, Efimia D. 2020. Who Am I? (Mis)Identity and the Polis in Oedipus Tyrannus. Hellenic Studies Series 86. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_KarakantzaED.Who_am_I.2020.


5. I am Oedipus: Reframing the Question of Identity

Πάντες ἄνθρωποι τοῦ εἰδέναι ὀρέγονται φύσει. σημεῖον δ’
ἡ τῶν αἰσθήσεων ἀγάπησις· καὶ γὰρ χωρὶς τῆς χρείας
ἀγαπῶνται δι’ αὑτάς, καὶ μάλιστα τῶν ἄλλων ἡ διὰ τῶν
ὀμμάτων. οὐ γὰρ μόνον ἵνα πράττωμεν ἀλλὰ καὶ μηθὲν
μέλλοντες πράττειν τὸ ὁρᾶν αἱρούμεθα ἀντὶ πάντων ὡς εἰπεῖν
τῶν ἄλλων. αἴτιον δ’ ὅτι μάλιστα ποιεῖ γνωρίζειν ἡμᾶς
αὕτη τῶν αἰσθήσεων καὶ πολλὰς δηλοῖ διαφοράς.

Aristotle Metaphysics 980a22–28

All men naturally desire knowledge. An indication of this is our esteem for the senses; for apart from their use we esteem them for their own sake, and most of all the sense of sight. Not only with a view to action, but even when no action is contemplated, we prefer sight to practically all the other senses. The reason for this is that of all the senses sight best helps us to know things, and reveals many distinctions. [1]


The “who am I?” has now been answered. The after in the reconstitution of the hero’s identity culminates in the new horror of Oedipus’ self-blinding. As we embark on defining the “I am Oedipus” several questions arise. [
2] Why does Oedipus blind himself? Is the motivation for his action consistent with his character, in keeping with the man we have come to know as “our” Oedipus? Additionally, is this an act of violent impulse, or does it result from a calculated appraisal of what the future holds for him? Does Oedipus clarify his action in a manner consonant with the renowned intelligence and determination that characterized his previous life? It is obvious that, in the light of this barrage of questions, the issue of identity has shifted focus. From line 1180 onward Oedipus emerges in full command of his powers to face a difficult new question: how do I now proceed in the knowledge that I have committed parricide and incest? He enters again the moral public space of all difficult decisions, where we act as social beings. He also repositions himself in the webs of interlocution—where this time he is questioned, and where he responds with a lengthy justification of his actions.

5.1 Self-Blinding

[ANTIGONE]:
WE BEGIN IN THE DARK
AND BIRTH IS THE DEATH OF US

Anne Carson, Antigonick


I agree with Alister Cameron’s view that the self-blinding is the central act of the denouement of the play, the transformation through which Oedipus becomes the “actor of his own fate,” and that it “is made to represent and somehow contain all the other acts which have gone before it.” [
3] Oedipus declares himself to be the sole agent [4] of the blinding (1331–1332):

ἔπαισε δ’ αὐτόχειρ νιν οὔ-
τις, ἀλλ’ ἐγὼ τλάμων.

And no other hand struck my eyes, but my own miserable hand!


The decision to shut himself off from the light of the day is confirmed the moment Oedipus understands the whole truth. The connection between the inner knowledge and the external light, as well as the symbolism of the reversal of this analogy, has become a commonplace in almost all analyses of the play. I shall only remark on how this reversal (a topos in the Sophoclean corpus) is exquisitely captured in Ajax’ apostrophe to darkness: that it is his own light (σκότος, ἐμὸν φάος, Ajax 394) that allows us room to see Oedipus’ apostrophe to light (ὦ φῶς, τελευταῖόν σε προσβλέψαιμι νῦν, 1183) as a possible statement of death. Thus we may understand why Oedipus, in a fit of fury, asks for a sword from the palace servants who witnessed Jocasta’s retreat to the nuptial chamber—is the victim to be Jocasta or himself? [
5] However, death by the sword is not how Sophocles envisages the climax of his narrative. The lifeless body of Oedipus’ wife and mother is already hanging there when he rushes in; all that remains for him is to release her body from the noose, and lay it upon the ground before putting his eyes out with the golden pins of her garment. [6] Everything is decided and executed within a split second. Then and there, we learn for the first time why Oedipus mutilates himself, as reported by the messenger (1271–1274):

… ὁθούνεκ’ οὐκ ὄψοιντό νιν
οὔθ’ οἷ’ ἔπασχεν οὔθ’ ὁποῖ’ ἔδρα κακά,
ἀλλ’ ἐν σκότῳ τὸ λοιπὸν οὓς μὲν οὐκ ἔδει
ὀψοίαθ’, οὓς δ’ ἔχρῃζεν οὐ γνωσοίατο.

… that they should not see his dread sufferings or his dread actions, but in the future they should see in the darkness those they never should have seen, and fail to recognize those he wished to know.

These considerations evoke the notion of sight and the action of seeing in their cultural, social, and ideological context. Oedipus is overwhelmed with the dread of seeing others and witnessing how he is seen by them. The culturally informed way of seeing and being seen fits into an exploration of the constructed notion of the “gaze.” This notion is widely explored by feminist critics, who point to the male gaze directed toward women and their bodies that transforms them into objectified sources of erotic pleasure. Starting from Freud’s scopophilia, introduced in Three Essays on Human Sexuality, which depicts the pleasure derived from looking at erotic objects, [9] and moving to Lacan, who gave theoretical force to the gaze (le regard), [10] contemporary cinema studies [11] explore the male gaze as the active power that looks. [12] Of course, this “male gaze” and “erotic pleasure” have no part here. [13] But the “gaze,” that is, the culturally specific way of looking at things and persons, and the way we understand people looking at us, falls into social categories that interest me in the Oedipus Tyrannus; “a gaze can never be neutral and … every act of seeing involves a ‘way of seeing.’ ” [14] We should also bear in mind that even before the proliferation of cinema studies—from the 1970s onward—and feminist criticism, the notion of “gaze” could be detected in works on classical literature. I take the classic work by Bruno Snell, The Discovery of the Mind, especially the chapter on “Homer’s View of Man,” as a case in point. [15] In this much-cited study, the author makes us “see” the many different ways that Homeric heroes “look”: the “fixing gaze” [16] of a warrior, the uncanny deadly stare simulating that of a dragon, [17] and the gleam in the eyes that somebody else sees in us. [18] So it comes as no surprise that Helen Lovatt’s 2013 book focuses entirely on The Epic Gaze. [19]

Oedipus’ following justification of the act is lengthy (1369–1415), leaving no room for doubts about his motivation. The blinding could have been characterized as an act of passion, but this would presuppose an impulsive reaction to extreme emotions. Obviously, Oedipus is filled with pain, sorrow, and shame as he enters the palace and the nuptial chamber; his self-blinding, however, appears well-calculated and is clearly reasoned in his reply to the chorus (1371–1378):

ἐγὼ γὰρ οὐκ οἶδ’ ὄμμασιν ποίοις βλέπων
πατέρα ποτ’ ἂν προσεῖδον εἰς Ἅιδου μολών,
οὐδ’ αὖ τάλαιναν μητέρ’, οἷν ἐμοὶ δυοῖν
ἔργ’ ἐστὶ κρείσσον’ ἀγχόνης εἰργασμένα.
ἀλλ’ ἡ τέκνων δῆτ’ ὄψις ἦν ἐφίμερος,
βλαστοῦσ’ ὅπως ἔβλαστε, προσλεύσσειν ἐμοί;
οὐ δῆτα τοῖς γ’ ἐμοῖσιν ὀφθαλμοῖς ποτε·

For I do not know with what eyes I could have looked upon my father when I went to Hades, or upon my unhappy mother, since upon them both I have done deeds that hanging could not atone for. Then, could I desire to look upon my children, since their origins were what they were? Never could these eyes have harboured such desire!

I take these words at face value. Death, a solution entertained by the chorus, could not erase Oedipus’ dread of the moment of looking, sight intact, upon his parents in Hades. Nor is it a lesser surrogate for death, for even death does not expunge his deeds. Oedipus clearly says that he wants to shut himself off from the world; mutilating the senses connecting him to this world is his method. Sight is the paramount sense, but he would also willingly destroy his ears so as to block the hearing as well (1386–1388):

… ἀλλ’ εἰ τῆς ἀκουούσης ἔτ’ ἦν
πηγῆς δι’ ὤτων φραγμός, οὐκ ἂν ἐσχόμην
τὸ μὴ ἀποκλῇσαι τοὐμὸν ἄθλιον δέμας,
ἵν’ ἦ τυφλός τε καὶ κλύων μηδέν·

Why, if there had been a means of blocking the stream of hearing through my ears, I would not have hesitated to shut off my wretched self, making myself blind and deaf.


Oedipus wishes to reduce himself to a mutilated body, nurturing his wounds in the isolation of a blindness safeguarded by a blockading of his senses. Thus Oedipus’ body becomes doubly mutilated: the original “act” was performed by Laius, the second by Oedipus himself in full consciousness of his action. This last corporeal scarring is equivalent to Oedipus’ giving himself the second feature of his identity, with which he will be known around the world: in a sense, one can discern a “cyclic” formation in Oedipus’ life, which results in a consolidation of the corporeal “dimensions” of his identity. [
28] Performing the second mutilation is the only way to make his earthly existence bearable, and also a way to transport himself to a place where sorrow can no longer touch him, as he himself declares (1389–1390): τὸ γὰρ / τὴν φροντίδ’ ἔξω τῶν κακῶν οἰκεῖν γλυκύ (“it is a joy to live with one’s thoughts beyond the reach of sorrow”). Oedipus languishes, disconnected from the world, while awaiting the announcement of his punishment.

5.2 Who is to Blame? Apollo, Oedipus, or Shared Responsibility?

It is said that whosoever the gods wish to destroy,
they first make mad. In fact, whosoever the gods wish
to destroy, they first hand the equivalent of a stick with
a fizzing fuse and Acme Dynamite Company written
on the side. It’s more interesting, and doesn’t take so long.

Terry Pratchett, Soul Music

It hardly needs to be said that critics have responded to these issues so diversely that their conclusions cover a disparate spectrum, from one deterministic pole that sees Oedipus as a puppet, a victim trapped in the net of a cruel destiny, to the opposite pole where the protagonist has substantial command over his own life choices; in the latter, divine action remains closeted in the background or is identified with authorial intentions. The scope of the present chapter does not allow for this diversity to be tackled individually or even an attempt at broad summarization. However, I will engage in a dialogue with some of the most influential recent critical approaches, for I think we need to reframe not only the old questions but the new answers as well.

I will interrogate Cairns’s argument by pointing to an interesting feature of Sophocles’ diction here, often ignored by commentators; in typical Sophoclean fashion, in just two lines (1331–1332) we have accumulative terms denoting full agency for the action of self-blinding. Oedipus takes full responsibility of the action per se, with the words αὐτόχειρ (= with my own hand), οὔτις (= no one), and ἀλλ᾽ ἐγὼ (= no one else but me). The obdurate repetition of the idea “no one else but me” seems to consolidate a fully-fledged αὐτοχειρία, thus making Oedipus the conscious agent of the action. Thus we can talk about a “shared responsibility” implied in the phrases Ἀπόλλων τάδ’ ἦν and αὐτόχειρ νιν οὔ /τις, ἀλλ’ ἐγώ. This is undermined, however, by Cairns, who argues that the self-blinding (as well as the parricide that is connected with the blinding via the word αὐτόχειρ) “are of the same order, carried out by a human being acting for intelligible human reasons but simultaneously fulfilling prophecies whose logic entails that these aspects of the future, at least, are necessary and unavoidable. These prophecies, moreover, are presented not merely as objects of divine knowledge but “projects of divine intervention.” [43] So, even if Oedipus (hypothetically) did not want to blind himself (as with the actions of parricide and incest, which he committed unwillingly), Apollo would have ensured “that it should still happen despite human opposition.” [44] In this sense, the self-blinding becomes part of a “grand design” that encompasses all divine interventions.

It is obvious that Patroclus pursues his own kleos and acts on the battlefield not as Achilles’ proxy but on his own motivations. When Patroclus has forced the panicking Trojans back from the ditch protecting the Greek camp and towards their walled city (16.293, 366–367), he intercepts them and presses them back towards the ships once more (16.395). This instigates the intervention of Sarpedon, which will trigger a series of causally related deaths—Sarpedon will be killed by Patroclus, Patroclus by Euphorbus and Hector, Hector by Achilles—because the clear objective of Book 16 is to rouse the disengaged Achilles back into the battle. [53] It is obvious that what we read here is the poet’s plan, the narratological plan that overrides the plan of Zeus. I shall remind you here that what we consider “the plan of Zeus,” which was formulated in the promise to Thetis, is a rather general condition indicating that Zeus will temporarily favor the Trojans to force the Achaeans to realize Achilles’ importance and beseech him to return to battle. This condition has been already met in Book 9 when the members of the Embassy (following the orders of Agamemnon) offer him a full recompense and entreat his return. It is then that Achilles, adding a further condition, “modifies” the plan of Zeus: he will relent his anger and return to the fray only when the fire reaches his own ships. By Book 15, the parallel plans of Zeus and Achilles have reached an irresolvable impasse (for Achilles remains inactive, despite the proximity of the fire to his own ships) that will be broken only by Patroclus’ intervention, which triggers an inevitable chain of events leading to his own death, to that of Hector, and finally, to the homilia of Priam and Achilles that forms the closure of our Iliad. [54]

Along the same lines, in the vein of narratology and semiotics, John Peradotto in his “Disauthorizing Prophecy” approaches the oracle of Apollo in Oedipus Tyrannus:


Given that the oracle represents the narrative, then “the actions of Apollo are identical to the constitutive actions of the author, while those of Oedipus, Jocasta, and the rest are but products of those constitutive actions.” [
61] Furthermore, “what Apollo ‘does’ in the OT,” the author argues, “is something that the poet does directly; what Oedipus ‘does’ is something the poet does indirectly.” The divine activity in Oedipus Tyrannus is reflected in the “direct operation of the poet on the plot,” for which no motivation resembling the way humans act is required. [62] It can also help us to explain, in my view, the trouble we experience in attributing an act of hybris to Oedipus that would conveniently and theologically justify his fall. The many and controversial analyses of the second stasimon, which introduces the notion of the tyrant and his hybris, as well as the many attempts to find Oedipus at fault either in his aggressive attitude to Teiresias and Creon, or in his intellectual pride, point to the futility of any attempt to construct a clear and unobstructed course leading from an “angry,” “offended,” or simply “revengeful” deity to the fallen mortal. [63]

My argument thus far has depicted Oedipus as a conscious human agent and a strong evaluator who takes full responsibility for his actions. The self-blinding is the conscious attempt to mutilate his sight, rendering the socially constructed way of seeing and being seen impossible; he cannot endure the gaze of the others, be it his family or his fellow citizens. At the same time, he cannot endure the complete change of his own gaze. The superiority of a socially accepted benign king is forever destroyed, for he can no longer command respect in the public space. Oedipus has been transfigured from a respected king into a social outcast. In the actions of seeing and being seen, his transgressions and the ensuing public shame will be constantly re-enacted. The decision to blind himself is truly his own.

Thus, in the famous lines Ἀπόλλων τάδ’ ἦν and αὐτόχειρ νιν οὔ/τις, ἀλλ’ ἐγὼ, I attribute to Oedipus his own clear share of responsibility. It remains to be seen how a person, such as the Sophoclean Oedipus, can act freely as a human agent and exert his own will in the context of the entire tragedy from within the circumscribed confines of his story given by the tradition. This will be addressed in the next section by revisiting the influential article of J.-P. Vernant, “Intimations of Will in Greek Tragedy” and moving on to re-evaluate the notions of will, agent, and the self, which—to my mind—are highly applicable to Oedipus. Sophocles has produced a play where he confronts the ultimate challenge of depicting a person with strength of will and remarkable determination despite the inflexible confines of the tradition that engendered his story.

5.3 Oedipus as a Human Agent

ἔοικε δή … ἄνθρωπος εἶναι ἀρχὴ τῶν πράξεων

it seems that it is the human being who is the origin of his actions

Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics 1112b31–32


Up until now, critics have been at great pains to prove the degree of divine intervention in human affairs in Oedipus Tyrannus. I suggest taking the reverse course in our critical thinking; what if, instead of trying to determine how much the divine influences the course of events in the play, we examine the opposite perspective and try to establish the degree of human agency manifested in the play? In doing so, we should take the existence of the gods, together with the theological system they comprise, as an indispensable and constitutive part of the tradition within which Sophocles and his contemporary Athenians lived, breathed, and wrote. Sophocles composes a play that acknowledges this tradition; how could he do otherwise? Nevertheless, within this tradition, he creates a play that studies the boundless limits of human action. Sophocles constructs his Oedipus as an intelligent human being making decisions after intense deliberation, despite the circumscribed boundaries of his life; here, the playwright faces a challenge greater than in any other traditional narrative.

In what follows, I suggest a different perspective for interpreting the divine and human actions in Oedipus Tyrannus. In doing this, I shall revisit and re-evaluate the influential approach of Vernant regarding “Intimations of the Will in Greek Tragedy,” where he examines the manifestation of the will in Greek tragedy as a culturally determined notion also linked to the categories of action and agent. [64] Here the emphasis is put on the judicial reforms and institutions of fifth-century Athens that explain, according to the critic, the emergence of the human subject as a discrete entity, and their decision-making and consequent actions, as we move from the “objective crime” (of the Homeric poems) to the “subjective responsibility” for transgressions as formulated by Aristotle a century later. [65] So the individual in fifth-century Athens emerges as “subject to the law,” [66] a political subject. Seductive as this idea might be, it is the first point to attract my criticism. The second is related to the way that Vernant sees the tragic agent as “still limited, indecisive, and vaguely defined,” [67] presenting “internal inconsistencies” due to the incomplete transition between older and newer concepts of justice, between Homer and the tragic genre. I will argue, on the contrary, that Oedipus can be seen as “an embodied individual,” whose particular ethical role is realized within his social and political context, and is neither “fragmented” nor “incomplete,” but a unitary entity, a bound self. [68] This is largely connected with the notion of identity, and “what it is to be a human agent,” [69] which has been the line of my argument throughout this book.

As I proceed to discuss the notion of the self as a non-fragmented individual, well established by the fifth century BCE (which, to my mind, should be considered as the foundation upon which Greek tragedy is formed), many collateral, but significant, issues will emerge and be tackled. First, the notion of the “will,” which is a highly problematic term when applied to ancient texts before the Stoics—let alone the notion of the “free will.” Equally problematic is to impose later assumptions about the will on the ancient notion (or better, on the notions that fall within the spectrum of our contemporary concept of the will), thus creating confusion and misunderstandings, to the extent of seriously undermining the concomitant notions of human agency and decision making in classical Greek thought, especially when a contemporary reader seeks to identify a sequence of events purely human in attribution. Second, I will discuss the interconnection between, and transition from, the “objective crime” of the Homeric poems to the “subjective responsibility” of the tragic genre, thought by Vernant to be an “incomplete transition.” I will raise the issue that, in cultural history, the coexistence of “old” and “new” structures of thought can be explained not as a deficiently resolved process needing consummation, but as a moment of creation (as Castoriadis defines it), when the old and new coexist in variable proportions and relations, positing a new eidos, a new “form” in the strongest and fullest sense. [70] Finally, this strand of the argument will conclude that Oedipus’ actions in Oedipus Tyrannus are better explained by exploring the notion of the self and the concomitant dimensions of human agency that present a remarkable consistency, determination, and independence despite the constraints imposed by the divine oracle.

5.3.1 The notion of the will

Along with Vernant, who raises questions arising from the notions of will (and the related notions of agency, intention, volition, and the like), we should note that the notion of the will is highly problematic (let alone the notion of a free will) when used before the Stoics, and consequently its use should be redefined in the context of Greek tragedy. When we, like Vernant, turn to Aristotle for enlightenment, [85] we realize, with the guidance of Michael Frede, [86] that the philosopher did not have a notion of the will, for he lacked the appropriate notion of choice in the way that a modern person would understand it. Not all of our actions are due to a mental event (a choice or decision to act); there is the case of “the choice without will” [87] when acting against reason (or on a non-rational desire). This is attributed to a failure of “training, practice, exercise, discipline, and reflection”—in short, to a lack of education or upbringing that “accounts for akratic action (ἀκρασία).” [88] Closer to what we understand as will are the Aristotelian notions of “willing or wanting something” (βούλεσθαι / βούλησις) and the notion of “choice” (προαιρεῖσθαι / προαίρεσις). [89] This latter is a “special form of willing” for two reasons. First, because “choosing” depends strictly on whether it is up to us (ἐφ᾽ ἡμῖν) to do something or make something happen; [90] but the “capacity to do things” does not necessarily coincide with “willing to do things.” [91] Second, because choices can be explained “in terms of the attachment of reason to the good” [92] and not (again necessarily) in terms of the will. Failure in the development of an individual human nature (due to immature development of character) results in failure to attain the good, something related, not to the will, but rather to the conditions of one’s life (often beyond the control of the individual). Moreover, “just as there is no notion of a will in Aristotle, there is also no notion of freedom”; [93] this makes the reference to a free will in classical texts even more problematic. In the Aristotelian view, there are regularities in this world that dictate a course of action. The celestial cosmos is “governed by a strict regularity,” [94] while human affairs, although presenting a certain latitude for free action, are again somehow circumscribed “because of imperfect realizations of human nature”; [95] only the virtuous person can make the appropriate choices.

5.3.2 Subjective responsibility and individualism

As I advocated earlier, at the end of the sixth century BCE there was a new social signification attached to the abstractions of “Athens” and “Athenians,” which pointed to the will of the Athenians to become an empowered body politic that could collectively effect change in the public realm. The Athenians wished to have an independent polis not adherent to Sparta; they also refused to think of themselves (to imagine themselves, in Castoriadian terminology) as clients to local aristocrats, nor did they tolerate tyranny. The political praxis during the turbulent years between 510 BCE (the abolition of tyranny) and 508 BCE (the Athenian Revolution and the ensuing Cleisthenian reforms) marks the autonomy of a collectivity in the process of developing strong ties between its members and, undoubtedly, creating a new civic identity. This civic identity, which marks the interconnection and interdependence between the individual subjectivity and the collective character of the Athenians, has been examined in chapter 3. I will only remind the reader here that a marked trait of the self in the polis is the accountability of the individuals to their community. The self in this sense is so strongly political that it becomes much broader than Vernant’s political subject, who is principally subject to the law.

5.3.3 Divine and human Action: A new creation

Vernant contended, however, that in tragedy the transition between the older forms of moral action and the self and the new innovations are not clearly demarcated [112] because of an incomplete process. I think that, despite Vernant’s strong structuralist methodology, this idea resonates with an older trend of historicism that sees evolution as a mainly linear progression—the old will be gradually replaced by the new in a continuous line of successive forms and structures. This view of cultural history is no longer adequate, which constitutes the second parameter of the critique that I bring to the discussion. At any given moment in a human society, structures (intellectual, ethical, emotional, behavioral, and so on) exist as a synthesis of various strata, where the old and new exist synchronically in varying proportions and relations. When we come to classical Athens and the tragic genre, we can understand the co-existence of the divine and the human, not as an incomplete transition, but as a new “creation” in the sense that Castoriadis defines it; not as a new discovery of something that was there before, undiscovered, but as a process of “constituting the new,” [113] which is an “active constitution,” during which the Athenians re-conceptualize their “social imaginary significations.” [114] In the words of Castoriadis:


For Castoriadis, society “institutes itself in instituting the world of significations that is its own, in correlation to which, alone, a world can and does exist for it”; [
116] in other words, “society brings into being a world of significations and itself exists in reference to such a world.” [117] Of course, this has to be understood in the context of the process of the “self-institution” of Athenian society, where an institution, which is a socially sanctioned symbolic network, comprises both a functional and an imaginary component. [118] Since Greek tragedy in particular is one of the main domains of the imaginary, where the re-conceptualization of social significations are formed and explored, we would expect to find there this active creation that comprises the notion of self, the individual, and the agent in the socio-historical context of fifth-century Athens. Human agency presupposes autonomy, and refers to “the relationship between the individual and society, and to the individuals’ self-constitution within their specific social context in order to become subjects of action capable of transforming their reality.” [119] This creation, of course, acknowledges the “pre-political” (in Castoriadis’s sense) existence of the gods and their oracles, and the constraints they impose on mortal lives. The “pre-political” is never fully eradicated, and under certain circumstances will resurface again, when classical political thought weakens in the face of other structures, where the active citizen is replaced by an individual subject to a Hellenistic king or Roman emperor. However, in Greek tragedy, when we are still en plein classical thought, viable forms of the individual, in correlation with the collective, are tried out so as to ensure the continuation of the unobstructed life of the polis. To this end, the social significations should be re-imagined or thought of and consequently sustained or modified; [120] “whatever has been imagined strong enough,” argues Castoriadis, “to shape behavior, speech, or objects can, in principle, be re-imagined (represented) by somebody else.” [121]

5.3.4 Rounding up the Argument

I conclude this excursus into the pressing and contentious issue of human agency and the subjective individuality that is embedded in the tragic situation in Oedipus Tyrannus (as is in most Greek tragedies) by stating that Oedipus is nowhere powerless in the hands of his gods, despite the renowned constraints to his life. In Oedipus Tyrannus the struggle of the individual in articulating his reasoning while rationally debating his position in this world, and notably in the quest for his identity, emerges with great clarity. Sophocles’ Oedipus is not bound by a family curse as in Aeschylus. He commits crimes in ignorance (agnoia), for which he alone is responsible to the extent that he does not understand the signs of his identity (which are intentionally blurred). In a contemporary court of law he would have been absolved. He uses all his intellectual powers to understand and act according to a set of values that constitute a life worth living. He is a strong evaluator and a moral agent because what he does, he does with courage, intelligence, and determination. He confronts all the constraints of his life with the utmost fortitude. If at the end he falls, he does so with his immense dignity intact.

Footnotes

[ back ] 1. Trans. Tredennick.

[ back ] 2. The self-blinding occurs also in Aeschylus, but it is attributed to the family curse, which is emphasized in the Aeschylean trilogy—the curse that follows Laius’ rape of Chrysippus and that becomes a family Erinys (Segal 2001:26; for the various versions of the self-blinding in ancient and later traditions, see also Edmunds 1985:15–16).

[ back ] 3. 1968:105 and 116.

[ back ] 4. To preempt any objections to my ignoring the immediately previous lines (Ἀπόλλων τάδ’ ἦν, Ἀπόλλων, φίλοι, / ὁ κακὰ κακὰ τελῶν ἐμὰ τάδ’ ἐμὰ πάθεα, 1329–1330) that indicate Apollo’s complicity to the act, I would state here that this issue will be dealt with at length in the following section (5.2, pp. 125-133), where the entire passage is discussed.

[ back ] 5. Segal 2001:124; Edmunds 1985:15n75.

[ back ] 6. See also chapter 4.5 above (pp. 80–81) about the erotic/sexual connotations of this act over the body of Jocasta.

[ back ] 7. Sorabji 2006: “As for participation in community, I stress … , in opposition to Descartes, that the infant acquires its idea of ‘what I am looking at’ only in a social exchange and hand in hand with the idea of what another is looking at, and I commend analogous insights in the Greeks” (49; emphasis the author’s).

[ back ] 8. Taylor 1989:15.

[ back ] 9. “Scopophilia” (“pleasure in looking”) is coined to translate Freud’s term Schaulust (Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality in The Penguin Freud Library, vol. 7 (1977 [1905]), 69–70), and it is used in the case of his patient known as the “The Rat Man,” who has a “burning and tormenting curiosity to see the female body” (Notes on a Case of Obsessional Neurosis, in The Penguin Freud Library, vol. 9.2 (1991 [1909]), 41–42).

[ back ] 10. One of the four sexual drives, according to Lacan, is the scopic drive (the erogenous zone is the eyes, the partial object is the gaze, and the verb is to “see”), linking scopophilia with the appreciation of the other (Lacan 1978:183, 1990:86).

[ back ] 11. The advent of the seminal paper by Laura Mulvey “Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema,” published in Screen (16.3:6–18) in 1975, opened the way for “gaze” studies in their cinematic and other artistic contexts to flourish.

[ back ] 12. Salzman-Mitchell 2005:7.

[ back ] 13. Unless we consider the Freudian equation of self-blinding to self-castration, see George Devereux’s classic paper in 1973 “The Self-blinding of Oidipous in Sophocles’ Oidipous Tyrannos,” Journal for Hellenic Studies 93:36–49.

[ back ] 14. Mary Devereaux, as cited by Salzman–Mitchell 2005:11.

[ back ] 15. Pages 1–22 of the English translation. In this seminal study, originally published in 1946, we hear of the many ways that a Homeric person “sees” because of the great variety of verbs denoting vision, and the operation of sight: ὁρᾶν, ἰδεῖν, λεύσσειν, ἀθρεῖν, θεᾶσθαι, σκέπτεσθαι, δέρκεσθαι, παπταίνειν, some of which had gone out of use in classical Greek (1–2). The interesting thing is that most of the verbs do not describe the function of sight as such, but the specific way of looking at something, or the specific quality of a certain glance or gaze, a perspective that has become in later studies the notion of “gaze.”

[ back ] 16. Observe the telling titles of chapters 2 and 3 of the book by Salzman–Mitchell A Web of Fantasies: “Intrusive Gaze” and “Fixing Gaze.”

[ back ] 17. The Homeric verb is δέρκεσθαι, cognate with δράκων, denoting a “visual attitude, and does not hinge upon the function of sight as such” (Snell 1946:3). “Δέρκεσθαι is also used with an external object; in such a case, the present would mean: ‘his glance rests upon something,’ and the aorist: ‘his glance falls on an object,’ ‘it turns toward something,’ ‘he casts his glance on someone’ ” (2–3). Of course, the petrifying gaze of the Gorgon is also much explored in contemporary scholarship.

[ back ] 18. Such is one of the meanings of δέρκεσθαι: “the gleam of the eye as noticed by someone else” (Snell 1946:2), as well as the verb λεύσσω, cognate to λευκός as “gleaming,” “white,” meaning “to see something bright” (3). When the verb is accompanied by expressions of joy (χαίρων, τερπόμενοι), then “it is clear … that this term too derives its special significance from a mode of seeing; not the function of sight, but the object seen, and the sentiments associated with the sight, give the word its peculiar quality” (3–4, my emphasis).

[ back ] 19. Some of Lovatt’s chapters have the following telling titles: “The Divine Gaze,” “The Mortal Gaze,” “The Female Gaze,” and on warriors especially, “The Assaultive Gaze.” The Roman gaze is explored by Brian Krostenko in Cicero, Catullus and the Language of Social Performance (Chicago, 2001), especially in chapter V.2 “Looking down from the inside: the Roman Gaze.”

[ back ] 20. Revermann 2010:69–97.

[ back ] 21. Salzman–Mitchell 2005:7. I transfer the meaning from the gender power relations to which the quote refers, to power relations in general.

[ back ] 22. See also Finglass (2018 ad 1369–1415) commenting on the passage as a “closely reasoned justification for his self-blinding.”

[ back ] 23. Taylor 1985:25.

[ back ] 24. Ibid. 26.

[ back ] 25. Ibid. 35: “On the contrary they are articulations of our sense of what is worthy, or higher, or more integrated, or more fulfilling, and so on. But as articulations, they offer another purchase for the concept of responsibility.”

[ back ] 26. Cameron 1968:105.

[ back ] 27. Edith Hall begins her analysis on the importance of human deliberation in Sophocles’ Theban plays (2012) with this very utterance by the chorus, and Oedipus’ response (313): “don’t give me any more advice” (μηδὲ συμβούλευ’ ἔτι, 1370). She concludes the chapter stating that even Teiresias, the intermediary between gods and mortals, “can say to Creon in Antigone, with full conviction, that, for humans in difficult situations, “good counsel is the most potent of assents” (1050).

[ back ] 28. I owe the remark on the double mutilation as part of Oedipus’ identity to my former student, Marietta Kotsafti, formulated in one of our numerous discussions on Oedipus, in and out the classroom.

[ back ] 29. 2013:69–72; see also chapter 3, pp. 33–36 above.

[ back ] 30. For the several endings of the story of Oedipus as recorded in various ancient sources, see Jebb 1887:xii–xxi; Segal 2001:24–32; Edmunds 1985:6–17, 47–57; Finglass 2018:13–27.

[ back ] 31. As I have argued also in chapter 4.9 above, p. 114.

[ back ] 32. The notion of free will and its controversy when used in the context of classical texts of the fifth century BCE is discussed at great length in the next chapter.

[ back ] 33. The “division of responsibility between Apollo and Oedipus is purposely imprecise” (Finglass 2018 ad 1329–1333). At any rate, it is common in ancient thought to combine “divine and human explanations for an event, even if overlapping and apparently mutually contradictory” (ibid.).

[ back ] 34. Kovacs 2009b:359–360.

[ back ] 35. Kovacs 2009b:363.

[ back ] 36. Note the multiple repetitions in the lines of Ἀπόλλων, κακά, and ἐμὰ marking the “passionate exclamation” of Oedipus. At first, it might seem that Apollo’s role is conceived “on a greater scale,” referring to the entire life of Oedipus. But since the participle τελῶν has an object (that is, τάδ’ … πάθεα), we may infer a divine involvement in the actual action of self-blinding. Whatever the case, the roles of both Apollo and Oedipus “receive considerable emphasis” in the passage (Finglass 2018 ad 1329–1333).

[ back ] 37. The question of the chorus is very specific and refers to the self-blinding. Of course, it can be assumed that the κακὰ could be an all-encompassing term that extends to all the sufferings of Oedipus’ life.

[ back ] 38. Cairns 2013:128.

[ back ] 39. Ibid.

[ back ] 40. Cairns 2913:129.

[ back ] 41. Cairns 2013:135.

[ back ] 42. Cairns 2013:136.

[ back ] 43. Cairns 2013:136; my emphasis.

[ back ] 44. Cairns 2013:138.

[ back ] 45. Cairns 2013:140.

[ back ] 46. Ibid.

[ back ] 47. Cairns 2013:142.

[ back ] 48. Ibid.

[ back ] 49. Cairns 2013:138.

[ back ] 50. Karakantza 2014:121–140.

[ back ] 51. Translated by Murray/Wyatt.

[ back ] 52. Attributing a clear motivation of his actions to the hero, de Jong 2001:xi.

[ back ] 53. Karakantza 2014:122–123, 129–130.

[ back ] 54. Karakantza 2014:122.

[ back ] 55. I have argued that Patroclus assimilates the negative paradigm of Meleager and “saves” Achilles from the embarrassment of going back to battle without receiving the honorary presents from the Achaeans. Scholarship thus far has compared Patroclus with Cleopatra, the wife of Meleager, for they are both suppliants to angry heroes, one persuading Meleager to fight, the other receiving permission to fight in Achilles’ stead. The essential common point of their stories, however, is that “the peril to his own chamber, that forced Meleager to return to fighting without honor (as Phoenix points out), has also reached the ships of the Achaeans and now threatens—one may assume—the ships and tents of the Myrmidons. … If it were not for Patroclus, the fire would have forced Achilles to resume fighting in a less-than-honorable return to battle” (Karakantza 2014:127; see also 127nn14–15).

[ back ] 56. Karakantza 2014:125.

[ back ] 57. Wilson 2007:152–153; Karakantza 2014:125.

[ back ] 58. From the standpoint of archaic ethics we have another factor that contributes to the death of Patroclus, and this is the temporal mental malfunction that is inferred in the notion of ἄτη (atê). The hero is seized by atê at that critical moment when he could have decided differently, not to pursue the Trojans further, where the poet allows explicitly a margin of free action. In that instant when Patroclus could still have the command of his own fate, a temporary mental blindness confuses his mind. There is a long debate about whether atê is due to divine intervention or describes a human error. In my paper I argue that the semantic spectrum of the word spans from describing divine intervention (in the two instances of the personified Ἄτη) to mainly human decision-making (as is later reflected in the nêpioi hetairoi and suitors in the Odyssey). Patroclus’ nêpiotês falls in the second category (Karakantza 2014:121, 131–134).

[ back ] 59. Karakantza 2014:122.

[ back ] 60. Peradotto 1992:10–11; emphasis by the author.

[ back ] 61. Peradotto 1992:9; emphasis by the author.

[ back ] 62. Quotations from Peradotto 1992:10.

[ back ] 63. See chapter 4.7 above, pp. 84–89.

[ back ] 64. Vernant 1988:150–151.

[ back ] 65. Vernant 1988:54–59. For the reference of the relevant Aristotelian sources, regarding this and other related issues, and the ensuing discussion, see the following pages of the current chapter.

[ back ] 66. Vernant 1988:82.

[ back ] 67. Ibid.

[ back ] 68. All the issues related to the notion of the self, and how it is connected to the polis are tackled at great length in chapter 3 above, pp. 25–37. I shall only reiterate here the definition of the self by Richard Sorabji (2006:32): “an embodied self plain to see, which has or owns both psychological and bodily characteristics.” He also argues that “I see no incompatibility between our interests in our own selves from the first-person perspective and an interest in our social duties and our objective existence as human beings” (49).

[ back ] 69. Taylor 1989:ix.

[ back ] 70. For an extensive discussion about the Castoriadian terms “creation” and eidos in history, see also chapter 2 above, pp. 13–14.

[ back ] 71. Vernant 1988:50. Vernant’s work is all the more remarkable, when one considers that his article was published nearly forty-five years ago, when the trend in classical scholarship (with a few notable exceptions) was toward a pervasive humanism resonating with an old-fashioned and out-of-date German Idealism, obliterating, as it were, all the differentiations and subtleties in concepts with which we are now familiar through new theories in philosophy, political and social sciences, gender studies, feminist thought, and poetics.

[ back ] 72. Vernant 1988:50–51.

[ back ] 73. Vernant 1988:54.

[ back ] 74. Ibid. This is one of the categories that constitute the modern concept of the will, according to Vernant; the others are: 1) individual as agent; 2) subjective responsibility taking the place of the objective crime: and 3) the degree of the interconnection between the intentions of the human agent and the deeds brought to accomplishment. All of these will be tackled in the course of the present chapter.

[ back ] 75. Discussed extensively above, at 5.2, pp. 130–132.

[ back ] 76. Karakantza 2014:122–123, 132–134.

[ back ] 77. Vernant 1988:63.

[ back ] 78. Vernant 1988:68.

[ back ] 79. καὶ γὰρ ἐπ’ αὐτῷ τῷ ἀγνοεῖν κολάζουσιν, ἐὰν αἴτιος εἶναι δοκῇ τῆς ἀγνοίας (Νicomachean Ethics 1113b 30–31); ὅσα δι’ ἀμέλειαν ἀγνοεῖν δοκοῦσιν, ὡς ἐπ’ αὐτοῖς ὂν τὸ μὴ ἀγνοεῖν (1114a1–2); also 1114a7–8; εἰ δὲ μὴ ἀγνοῶν τις πράττει ἐξ ὧν ἔσται ἄδικος, ἑκὼν ἄδικος ἂν εἴη (1114a12–13). Man as the origin of his actions (1113b15–20): τὸ δὲ λέγειν ὡς οὐδεὶς ἑκὼν / πονηρὸς οὐδ’ ἄκων μακάριος ἔοικε τὸ μὲν ψευδεῖ τὸ δ’ ἀλη- / θεῖ· μακάριος μὲν γὰρ οὐδεὶς ἄκων, ἡ δὲ μοχθηρία ἑκού- / σιον. ἢ τοῖς γε νῦν εἰρημένοις ἀμφισβητητέον, καὶ τὸν / ἄνθρωπον οὐ φατέον ἀρχὴν εἶναι οὐδὲ γεννητὴν τῶν πράξεων / ὥσπερ καὶ τέκνων (“The saying ‘No one is voluntarily wicked, nor involuntarily blessed’, seems partly false, and partly true. For no one is involuntarily blessed, but wickedness is voluntary; otherwise, we shall have to disagree with what we have just said, and deny that a human being is a first principle or the begetter of his actions as he is of his children,” trans. Crisp).

[ back ] 80. Vernant 1988:69.

[ back ] 81. Vernant 1988:82.

[ back ] 82. Karakantza 2013: “The provenance of atê could be divine, as in books 9 and 19 [of the Iliad], or primarily human, as is in the case of Patroclus. It seems that atê is directed by Zeus at mortals that have made themselves vulnerable to a certain error” (133); see also Yamagata 1991:9, 12 and 1994:57–60.

[ back ] 83. Vernant 1988:65.

[ back ] 84. Vernant 1988:59. See also Frede 2011:2–4, 157; Dihle 1982:45; Kahn 1988:234–259; Kenny 1979 passim. As for the precariousness in the notion of the will, Kahn begins his contribution in Dillon and Long 1979, titled “Discovering the Will: From Aristotle to Augustine,” as follows: “It is clear that there is a problem about the will in ancient philosophy, but it is not so clear just what the problem is. At one time it seemed that there was a general agreement that the notion of the will was lacking in Greek philosophy.” He then suggests that we need to consider what our concept of the will is, for we need to clarify this “before we start looking for traces of the will in antiquity, or looking for the gaps that show that this concept is lacking” (234–235). This is to acknowledge the long tradition of the investigation into the divergences or congruities of the notion since antiquity.

[ back ] 85. Vernant 1988:56–58.

[ back ] 86. Frede’s book was published posthumously in 2011 (edited by A. A. Long) as A Free Will: Origins of the Notion in the Ancient Thought.

[ back ] 87. Frede 2011:19–30; “not everything voluntary is an object of choice” and Nicomachean Ethics 1112a15.

[ back ] 88. Nicomachean Ethics 1141b21–1146b5 and 1145a2–1154b32; Eudemian Ethics 1223a37–1223b31 and 1246b13 (ἀκρασία); Frede 2011:24.

[ back ] 89. προαίρεσις (rational choice, or disposition to choose), βούλησις / βούλευσις (wish) and their interaction are explored in Νicomachean Ethics 1111b5–1112a17 and 1112a20–1113a15, respectively. See, in particular, the two following illustrative passages; first, Nicomachean Ethics 1111b26–30: ἔτι δ’ ἡ μὲν βούλησις τοῦ τέλους ἐστὶ μᾶλλον, ἡ δὲ προαίρεσις τῶν πρὸς τὸ τέλος, οἷον ὑγιαίνειν βουλόμεθα, προαιρούμεθα δὲ δι’ ὧν ὑγιανοῦμεν, καὶ εὐδαιμονεῖν βουλόμεθα μὲν καὶ φαμέν, προαιρούμεθα δὲ λέγειν οὐχ ἁρμόζει· ὅλως γὰρ ἔοικεν ἡ προαίρεσις περὶ τὰ ἐφ’ ἡμῖν εἶναι (“again, wish is more to do with the end, rational choice with what is conducive to the end; for example, we wish to be healthy, but we rationally choose things that will make us healthy; and we wish to be happy, and say that we do, but to claim that we rationally choose to be so does not sound right. For in general rational choice seems to be concerned with things that are in our power,” trans. Crisp). And second, βούλησις as deliberation (στοχασμός), Νicomachean Ethics 1112b11–16: βουλευόμεθα δ’ οὐ περὶ τῶν τελῶν ἀλλὰ περὶ τῶν πρὸς τὰ τέλη. οὔτε γὰρ ἰατρὸς βουλεύεται εἰ ὑγιάσει, οὔτε ῥήτωρ εἰ πείσει, οὔτε πολιτικὸς εἰ εὐνομίαν ποιήσει, οὐδὲ τῶν λοιπῶν οὐδεὶς περὶ τοῦ τέλους· ἀλλὰ θέμενοι τὸ τέλος τὸ πῶς καὶ διὰ τίνων ἔσται σκοποῦσι· (“We deliberate not about the ends, but about things that are conducive to ends. For a doctor does not deliberate about whether to cure, nor an orator about whether to persuade, nor a politician whether to produce good order; nor does anyone else deliberate about his end. Rather they establish an end and then go on to think about how and by what means it is to be achieved,” trans. Crisp). See also: Eudemian Ethics 1226a20–b30, 1227a5–18, 1226b2–20; Nicomachean Ethics 1113a10–11 and 1139a22–b5.

[ back ] 90. Νicomachean Ethics 1111b30, 1112a17, 1112a30, 1113b17–19; Frede 2011:27; Kahn 1988:240.

[ back ] 91. Not all voluntary actions result from proairesis: Nicomachean Ethics 1112a14–15, 1135b8–11; Eudemian Ethics 1223b38–1224a7 and 1226b34–36. Not every action with proairesis need follow actual deliberation: Nicomachean Ethics 1117a17-22.

[ back ] 92. Nicomachean Ethics 1112a15–1113a14 and 1113b3–4; Eudemian Ethics 1226a7–13; Eudemian Ethics 1226b9–20; Frede 2011:27, 157; Cooper 1975, chapter 1 passim.

[ back ] 93. Frede 2011:27.

[ back ] 94. Metaphysics 12.7–9. Frede 2011:28; Frede and Charles 2000 ad loc.

[ back ] 95. Frede 2011:30.

[ back ] 96. Frede 2011:48.

[ back ] 97. Frede 2011:32–33.

[ back ] 98. Frede 2011:46.

[ back ] 99. Ibid.

[ back ] 100. Hyman 2015:4.

[ back ] 101. Hyman 2015:1–2.

[ back ] 102. Hyman 2015:1.

[ back ] 103. Hyman 2015: “In the physical dimension the concepts of agent, power, and causation are attached; in the ethical dimension the concepts of voluntariness and choice; in the psychological dimension the concepts of desire, aim, and intention; in the intellectual dimension the concepts of reason, knowledge, and belief” (4).

[ back ] 104. Leonard 2015:9.

[ back ] 105. I would like to refer here to the interesting idea of the “self as a unitary entity,” which antedates Vernant’s “self as the political subject” by a century, dating back to the sixth century BCE in Ionia, and connected to widespread monetization and subsequent emergence of the unitary and unchanging Being (the first principle) of the physical philosophy, as argued by Richard Seaford in Money and the Early Greek Mind (2004) and, later, in his paper “Monetisation and the Genesis of the Western Subject” (2012); as well as in several other publications: “Tragedy, Ritual, and Money” (2004), “Money and the Confusion of Generations in Sophocles’ Oedipus Tyrannus” (2007), and “Money and Tragedy” (2008). In a sense, the “economic subject” of Seaford is posited against Vernant’s individual “subject to the law.”

[ back ] 106. Leonard 2005b:133.

[ back ] 107. Leonard 2005b:135.

[ back ] 108. Ibid.

[ back ] 109. Leonard 2015:9.

[ back ] 110. See chapters 2 and 3 above.

[ back ] 111. See also Valakas 2009:191.

[ back ] 112. Vernant 1988:79.

[ back ] 113. Castoriadis 1997a:132–133.

[ back ] 114. Castoriadis 1997a:341.

[ back ] 115. 1997a:133.

[ back ] 116. Castoriadis 1997a:359.

[ back ] 117. Ibid.

[ back ] 118. Castoriadis 1997a:132.

[ back ] 119. Tovar-Restrepo 2012:70.

[ back ] 120. I have argued elsewhere at length about the “correcting mechanism” of Attic tragedy in relation to the contemporary institutions of society, for tragedy addresses and affects their imaginary component. These institutions are the focal point of a society, such as the Athenian, that manifests itself as a societas instituans, and not a societas instituta (an instituting and not an instituted society; Castoriadis 1997a:369–373). The body of citizens create, deliberate, and constantly modify these very institutions by using several mechanisms, paramount among which is Attic tragedy; the end-point of this activity is the well-being of the citizens within their polis (Karakantza 2011a:22–25).

[ back ] 121. 1997b:270.

[ back ] 122. Taylor 1985:102–104, 106.

[ back ] 123. Taylor 1985:100.

[ back ] 124. Taylor 1985:106. In Oedipus Tyrannus what is meticulously studied are all the actions that comply with the “performance” criterion.

[ back ] 125. Rehm 2003, especially chapter 3, pp. 65–86.

[ back ] 126. In the renowned paper “On Misunderstanding the Oedipus Rex” (1966:42).

[ back ] 127. This is a well-known idea, beautifully formulated already by Doods in Pagan and Christian in an Age of Anxiety (1965:47).

[ back ] 128. Sorabji 2006: “the idea of being true to yourself” found in the late Stoics has Presocratic antecedents in Democritus’ exhortation “not to undertake activities beyond <one’s> own capacity and nature” and even in Socrates’ refusal to evade his execution as not being right for him, since he never left Athens before, except on military service (167). This falls within the wider issue of the idea of the individual persona that implies also an ethical dimension (157).

[ back ] 129. Rehm 2003:66; see also “in another culture, we might expect such a tragic vision to produce a sense of powerlessness before the multiple forces that lie beyond human control. But not in fifth- century Athens” (2003:67, my emphasis).

[ back ] 130. Cameron 1968:105.

[ back ] 131. Explored in chapter 4.7 above, pp. 84–99.