Definitions
The Central Thesis, with Two Clarifications
The Alexandrian classical model, as formalized in the very concept of the Pinakes of Callimachus, makes it explicit that a holistic perspective is a prerequisite for the application of the principle of selection. [11] To this extent, then, the formulation of Crates is unfair to the Alexandrians, since it implies that only the Pergamene classical model is truly holistic. As I will show, however, it may indeed be fair to say that the Pergamene classical model was more holistic than the Alexandrian, at least in the era of Crates. A case in point is the difference between Pergamene and Alexandrian approaches to Homeric verses suspected of being non-Homeric.
The specific piece of tradition that Richardson cites here comes from the Vita Marciana, which lists among Aristotle’s works not only his Homeric Questions (Ὁμηρικὰ ζητήματα) but also something called the ekdosis of the Iliad (ἡ τῆς Ἰλιάδος ἔκδοσις ἣν δέδωκε τῷ Ἀλεξάνδρῳ). [18]
The Library of Alexandria
As we read further in the narrative of Strabo (17.1.8 C794), Perdiccas was killed by his own men, and his retinue thereupon departed for Macedonia. Strabo then adds this detail about Ptolemy’s next move: τὸ δὲ σῶμα τοῦ Ἀλεξάνδρου κομίσας ὁ Πτολεμαῖος ἐκήδευσεν ἐν τῇ Ἀλεξανδρείᾳ ὅπου νῦν ἔτι κεῖται ‘but Ptolemy brought home [komizein] [31] the body [sōma] and gave it the proper ritual in Alexandria, where it still lies’ (again, 17.1.8 C794). [32] Strabo gives {195|196} further details concerning a glass display case in which the body of Alexander was kept during the geographer’s lifetime: this case was a replacement for an original golden sarcophagus stolen in the era of Ptolemy XI.
The Alexandrian Library’s appropriation of Aristotle as their very own proto-Peripatetic, as it were, became attenuated and modified with the passage of time. From around two hundred years after Strabo (born around 64 BCE) comes the following description of the prestige of the great libraries of the world:
This passage comes from a portion of the author’s work that survives only in epitomized form. Athenaeus, who flourished around 200 CE, was from Naukratis in Egypt, and his provenience signals a Hellenized Egyptian point of view in this listing of libraries. Athenaeus’ gallery of great men who possessed great libraries is an exercise in prestige by association, with a predictable climax: he reports that the collection of Aristotle was teleologically absorbed by the all-encompassing collection of the Ptolemies of Alexandria.
The “Vanished Library” of Aristotle [44]
The teleology of Strabo’s account is this: the library of Aristotle ends up in the capable hands of Tyrannion, described as a grammatikos and a ‘pro-Aristotelian’, who just happens to have been a teacher of Strabo’s. [47] This Tyrannion, who became a protégé of the likes of Caesar, Cicero, and Atticus, had studied in Rhodes under the distinguished Aristarchean scholar Dionysius Thrax. [48]
According to this even happier ending to the story, the “new” Peripatetics now have their own source of authority because they also possess their own “edited” text. In Strabo’s account, they had become less incomplete philosophers than the “old” Peripatetics, thanks to the “editing” by the Aristarchean scholar Tyrannion. In Plutarch’s account, by contrast, the “new” Peripatetics become complete philosophers thanks to the “editing” of the Peripatetic scholar Andronicus. The pinakes ‘catalogues’ of Andronicus must have superseded those of Callimachus—at least with reference to the corpus of Aristotle. [51]
These conflicting accounts, of course, leave many things unclarified. One thing, however, is quite clear in the account of Athenaeus that I have just cited: the Alexandrian Library’s initial holdings of Aristotle’s collection did not contain some of the originals or copies of Aristotle’s works that Apellicon later acquired. Athenaeus (5.211d) names Posidonius the Stoic as his source. [53] It is also clear from this account that Apellicon’s new acquisitions came from apotheta, ‘texts stored away in secured places’.
“Virtual Libraries”
Ironically, canonical sequencing was also a vital aspect of the performing arts, as we can see even from the incidental mention of a ‘fixed order’ (ordo) of competing reciters.
The idea of order in archaic Greek oral poetics finds expression by way of many metaphors: the order or integrity of a composition-in-performance is comparable to such artifacts as the weaving of a weaver, [81] the joining of a joiner or carpenter, [82] and even the text of a writer. [83] This {211|212} is not the place to examine at length the various applications of the last of these metaphors, that of the written text, a task that I have undertaken elsewhere. [84] Suffice it to observe here that the metaphor of performance as written text stems from cultural settings where oral and written poetics coexist. In such settings, the idea of order in the performing arts can be expressed in terms of an integral text or an integral body of texts, or even a reintegrated body of previously disintegrated texts. [85] An example of the last type of metaphor appears in Cicero’s account of the “Peisistratean Recension”: ‘he [Peisistratos] was the first to put in order the scrolls of Homer, which had previously been in disorder’. [86]
Crates of Mallos and the Library of Pergamon
The Reception of Homer in the Libraries
This is the way Nicanor also mentions it, and so too Crates in his Diorthōtika.
Let me anticipate my conclusions about this testimony: the reference to ‘Apellicon’s Iliad’ in this context goes to show that the same Apellicon {215|216} whose acquisition of select texts of Aristotle had led to the production of an “Aristoteles auctus” deserves credit for having also acquired a “Homerus auctus,” that is, a Homer text that contained extra verses not found in the texts available to, say, Aristarchus in Alexandria.
ἀνδράσιν ἠδὲ θεοῖς, πλείστην <τ᾿>ἐπὶ γαῖαν ἵησιν.
The first of these two verses as quoted by Plutarch corresponds to Iliad XIV 246 (with verse-initial Ὠκεανοῦ, continuing the syntax of verse 245 as we have it), while the second, “XIV 246a,” has been omitted from the text proper of standard modern editions of the Iliad. [123]
Crates’ Homer and the “Peisistratean Recension”
The ‘skewering’ refers to the Alexandrian procedure of marking with an obelos ‘skewer’ those verses that are to be athetized. [139] The mention of syllables may refer to the proverbial Aristarchean obsession with the minutiae of monosyllabic words, an obsession that some followers of Crates ridiculed. [140] Most important of all, the theme of an absence of {224|225} written recordings (fasti) of Orpheus and Homer reflects what appears to be an ongoing dispute between the followers of Crates and Aristarchus concerning the provenience of Homer.
Homer and the Library of Nysa
It would be misleading, I submit, to translate grammatikē, the subject taught by Aristodemus, simply as ‘grammar’. In view of the intellectual confluences that this list of notables represents, including figures like Apollonius, a Stoic acquaintance of Panaetius, pupil of Crates, and Menecrates, pupil of Aristarchus, and his son Aristodemus, teacher of Strabo, it stands to reason that the prestige of higher learning as conveyed by grammatikē must have concentrated on the classics, with primacy of place reserved surely for Homer. [162]
Epilogue: The “Vanished Ekdosis” of Aristotle’s Homer
The very idea of an Aristotelian ekdosis of Homer seems to have vanished in Pergamon as well: if this idea was not of much use for later Alexandrians like Aristarchus, it was of even less use to the Pergamenes, whose holistic approach to the text of Homer seems to have embraced even Orpheus and Musaeus.
The holism of the Library of Pergamon, as represented by Crates of Mallos, surely measured up to the standard set by Aristotle. [178]