Luraghi, Nino, and Susan E. Alcock, eds. 2003. Helots and Their Masters in Laconia and Messenia: Histories, Ideologies, Structures. Hellenic Studies Series 4. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_LuraghiN_AlcockS_eds.Helots_and_Their_Masters.2003.
Chapter 11. Reflections on helotic slavery and freedom
1. The nature and origins of helotry
2. Slavery, helotry and the invention of freedom
Anyone who finds himself at odds with a scholar of Professor Raaflaub’s eminence must pause and reconsider. In my case the urgency is acute in view of the fact that I relied heavily on Professor Raaflaub’s own meticulous earlier studies in the development of an important part of my argument on the origins of freedom (Raaflaub 1981; 1983; 1985). Happily, it turns out that he has misunderstood me, and while a few areas of disagreement certainly exist, we are far more in agreement on the central issues than he allows. In what follows, I will first note the important areas of agreement between us, then I will attempt to show that most our apparent disagreements are based on a misunderstanding of what I said.
If this sounds all too familiar to every student of Spartan helotry, it is because modern slaveholders were quick to see the parallels between their own versions of freedom and Herrenvolk democracy and those of the ancients, especially Sparta. What Luraghi wrote of the “set of practices of ritualized contempt by which the Spartiates’ produced a despicable collective identity for the helots,” holds exactly {306|307} true of modern Herrenvolk practices: that it was “a mirror image of the Spartiates’ image of themselves.” The most important reason for the study of ancient helotry, then, may well be the fact that the exalted, contradistinctive self-fashioning engendered by the Spartiates’ treatment of their helots was the historic prototype of what, until the early decades of the twentieth century, would remain the dominant model of Western freedom. {307|}
Bibliography
Footnotes