Between Thucydides and Polybius: The Golden Age of Greek Historiography

  Parmegianni, Giovanni. 2014. Between Thucydides and Polybius: The Golden Age of Greek Historiography. Hellenic Studies Series 64. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_ParmegianniG_ed.Between_Thucydides_and_Polybius.2014.


12. The Tools of Memory: Crafting Historical Legacy in Fourth-Century Greece

Sarah Ferrario

1. Introduction

Alexander’s public program, which involved image-making across a wide variety of media and contexts, was both ambitious and potent, but it was not without precedent. By his time, there were many ways for an eminent individual to script (to borrow from Thucydides 1.22.4) both a presentation for the contemporary public and a story for the ages. Some of these ‘tools of memory,’ {263|264} such as the commissioning of poetry, have their origins in the more distant past. Others, however, seem to have blossomed during the classical period. In the course of the fifth and earlier fourth centuries, individual historical responsibility and accomplishment gradually received greater acknowledgment both in the public sphere and in historical writing, and certain well-placed men in turn took advantage of the wider range of expressive resources available to them. By the time of Xenophon, outstanding individuals interested in shaping their own legacies could, for example, erect or accept statues or other monuments during their lifetimes, deliberately perform services that merited honorific inscriptions, and perhaps even, under certain circumstances, exercise some control over their reception in historiography.

2. The ‘Tools of Memory’ in Fourth-Century Greece

The developed concept of ‘historical memory’ as observed in the fourth century BCE finds its earliest literary roots in the heroic paradigm. [8] Achilles sees fighting at Troy as a necessary condition for gaining κλέος (‘fame’), and suggests that he can determine how he is remembered according to whether or not he remains at war (Iliad 9.412–416); Helen speculates that she and Paris will be ἀνθρώποισι . . . ἀοίδιμοι ἐσσομένοισι, “made famous in song for the generations to come” (Iliad 6.358). In Achilles’ reflections, therefore, recollection is bound up with deeds; in Helen’s, it is attached to words. But while logos may transform {264|265} ergon into memory, this process alone does not constitute the crafting of history, which by the fourth century can be articulated as requiring specific, as opposed to paradigmatic, content (Aristotle Poetics 9.1451a–b). [9] The specificity that Aristotle recognizes derives not only from the report of factual information, but also from historical context, the grounding of actions in a particular time, place, and set of circumstances. The fact that Aristotle famously takes Alcibiades as his exemplar is an appropriate reminder that an essential part of that context for the Greek individual of the classical era is his membership in his state. Indeed, the relationship between individual and polis can both enhance and limit opportunities for the creation of historically contextualized memory. During the fifth century, one place where this can be observed is in Pindar. [10]

3. The Legacy-Builders: Case Studies

The Athenians

That Conon was a conscious manipulator of public perception is suggested by the tradition that he advocated ‘autonomy’ for the Greek territories from which he and Pharnabazus expelled the Spartans during the middle years of the 390s. [35] Conon may have been acting in part out of expediency, but his ongoing rivalry with Thrasybulus was also a likely motivation for his careful attention to his image, as Strauss has observed, suggesting that “it is hard to avoid the {268|269} suspicion that Athens was not big enough for two liberators.” [36] The honors that took place upon Conon’s return from the victory at Cnidus are striking. Strauss collects the awards that Conon received (citing an inscription, the Agora statue, an Acropolis statue, and freedom from taxes), iterates the benefits that Conon bestowed in kind (new fortifications for the city, a temple to Cnidian Aphrodite, and a “festival liturgy for the entire citizenry”), and further notes that “the cities of Ionia, ever alert, exchanged statues of Lysander for images of the hero of Cnidus.” [37] Most significant here is the cycle of these honorific transactions. Conon, in a conscious, symbolic gesture, effectively proclaims to the Ionians the freedom that Athens failed to win for them a century before, during the great revolt against the Persians. In return, the Ionian Greeks grant Conon himself a series of honors expressed in tangible form. [38] Next, at Athens, Conon engages in public benefactions that are familiar—in kind if not perhaps in scope—from the fifth century. Like Nicias and even Alcibiades before him, he indulges, for example, in grand religious gestures: [39] the Piraeus temple of Cnidian Aphrodite is probably a tangible attempt to construct an historical legacy along with a building. [40] Most striking of all, however, would have been his large-scale support, both financial and logistical, for the rebuilding of Athens’ Long Walls. [41] The walls themselves would not only memorialize Conon’s patronage, but also in effect portray him as a re-founder of the Athenian Empire, [42] a Themistocles or Pericles reborn in an age that could offer him increased opportunities for memorialization as repayment for his achievements, his leadership, and his philanthropy.

The Thebans

Did Epaminondas in turn concern himself with his own historical legacy? He was perhaps best known for his daring military exploits, and in this both his immediate reputation and his lasting fame would have benefited not only from the growing tendencies of his age to honor individual generals, but also from the potential associations to be made with the Iliadic heroes. But one of the lasting monuments to his achievements in war was couched in highly traditional terms: his refoundation of Messene. Diodorus reads the city’s creation as being at least in part a strategic decision, due to the location of the site and Thebes’ ongoing conflicts with Sparta. But he also suggests, just beforehand, that Epaminondas was a man φύσει μεγαλεπίβολος ὢν καὶ δόξης ὀρεγόμενος αἰωνίου . . . τόπον δ ᾽ εὔθετον ἔχουσαν κατὰ τῆς Σπάρτης, “by his [very] character a planner of great things and grasping for eternal glory” (Diodorus 15.66.1). If there was any of this in Epaminondas’ motivations, casting himself in the role of colonial founder was a superb choice to ensure that he left his mark upon the historical record.

The Spartans

The commemoration of individual achievements in sanctuaries was by no means unknown at this point in Greek history. Individual dedications of arms and armor, both personal items and (especially) those taken from enemies, were a long-standing tradition; [73] extravagant and personalized ‘gifts’ to the gods also contributed to the reputations of their givers. [74] But the erection of individual monuments to historical successes in (especially) warfare seems to {274|275} have been somewhat restrained in the fifth century and often posthumous. [75] As Crane highlights, however, only some 75 years after the erasure of Pausanias’ epigram from the Serpent Column’s tripod, Lysander, during his lifetime and of his own accord, erected a spectacular, highly symbolic monument at Delphi. [76] The epigram from the base of Lysander’s statue may be preserved in a recut inscription from the later fourth century (ca. 350–300 BCE), in the now-expected elegiac couplets:

εἰκόνα ἑὰν ἀνέθηκεν [ἐπ’] ἔργωι τῶιδε ὅτε νικῶν
ναυσὶ θοαῖς πέρσεν Κε[κ]ροπιδᾶν δύναμιν
Λύσανδρος, Λακεδαίμονα ἀπόρθητον στεφανώσα[ς]
Ἑλλάδος ἀκρόπολ[ιν, κ]αλλίχορομ πατρίδα.
  ἐχσάμο ἀμφιρύτ[ου] τεῦξε ἐλεγεῖον⋮ Ἴων.

Lysander set up his image here on this monument when as conqueror
with swift ships he destroyed the Cecropidan force,
having crowned Lacedaemon undefeated,
the acropolis of Greece, homeland of beautiful dancing-grounds.
  Ion, from sea-girt Samos, created this poem.

Meiggs and Lewis 1969:288 no. 95 ( = FD III.1.50)


Like the Leuctra inscription from Thebes, this epigram emphasizes the historical contributions of its subject and employs poetical language. Despite the prominent mention of his state, the emphasis upon Lysander himself is striking for its reversal of commemorative expectations: under ordinary circumstances, it is the city that crowns the individual, but here it is Lysander who crowns Sparta. The monument itself apparently showed the god Poseidon crowning Lysander (Pausanias 10.9.7), and so if the epigram indeed belongs to the monument, the overall message would have portrayed Lysander as a kind of conduit to the divine on his city’s behalf. It might also have invoked the extensive reach of Lysander’s power and authority. On Attic document reliefs, for example, individuals who {275|276} had benefited the dêmos might be shown being crowned by Athena, patroness of the polis and returner in kind of benefits received. [
77] Casting Poseidon in a similar position here implies that Lysander is the benefactor of the sea itself. [78]

4. Legacy Building and Historiography

Herodotus’ preface suggests that historiography itself is a medium for the creation of memory, [88] and it is perhaps no surprise, therefore, that one of his own characters, Leonidas, appears to demonstrate awareness of that stance. Before the final struggle at Thermopylae, Herodotus examines Leonidas’ possible motivations for dismissing most of the other Greek contingents, noting in particular that μένοντι δὲ αὐτοῦ κλέος μέγα ἐλείπετο, καὶ ἡ Σπάρτης εὐδαιμονίη οὐκ ἐξηλείφετο, “great fame would be left him if he stayed, and the good fortune of Sparta would not be erased” (Herodotus 7.220.1–4, quotation at 7.220.2). Herodotus is clearly modeling his Leonidas here upon Achilles, given not only the reference to κλέος but also the idea of remaining at war to gain it, despite the promise of an early death. But this Spartan Achilles has wider-ranging concerns: beyond himself, he is also invested in the future of his city. Here, the character Leonidas seems not only to have taken the glory of the state to himself {277|278} in the manner of a Pindaric victor, [89] but even to have read the opening of the text in which he appears, given the connections between Leonidas’ thoughts here and the author’s words in the preface: [90] ὡς μήτε τὰ γενόμενα ἐξ ἀνθρώπων τῷ χρόνῳ ἐξίτηλα γένηται, μήτε ἔργα μεγάλα τε καὶ θωμαστά . . . ἀκλεᾶ γένηται, “so that what has happened among men may not fade with time, and that acts both great and amazing, some accomplished by Greeks and others by barbarians, may not lack fame” (Herodotus praef.). [91]

Herodotus here ascribes thoughts to Leonidas that seem to prove the essential function of the historian’s own mission. Leonidas may be sketched as a quasi-epic hero, but his concern for the εὐδαιμονίη of his state grounds him in historical reality, and Herodotus, through his diction, makes the character himself appear to understand that fact. For Leonidas, as for Herodotus, historiography is now the medium of memorialization, a path towards κλέος, and a means for crafting historical memory. It is too much to claim that the historical Leonidas was acting for the proverbial cameras, but it seems safe to say that the character Leonidas is certainly performing for the text—and that incidences like this might serve to remind readers and audiences of the memorializing potential of historiography.

Similar metatextual awareness seems to be displayed by some characters in Xenophon. An examination of Agesilaus and of Xenophon himself suggests that Xenophon the writer, much as he may admire the Spartan king, still demonstrates a pronounced difference between the character Agesilaus and the character Xenophon in their attitudes towards the construction of their respective historical legacies.

The lack of self-commemorative effort on the part of the Agesilaus character also emerges in vivid scenes such as the military preparations at Ephesus, complete with competitive games, intensive work upon military crafts, and religious processions. The sum total of the variety of activities feels not dissimilar to the shield of Achilles or the funeral games for Patroclus in the Iliad; [96] and like Achilles’ shield, which Hephaestus promises that men will gaze upon {279|280} with amazement (Iliad 18.466–467), Agesilaus makes Ephesus ἀξίαν . . . θέας (“deserving of sight,” Xenophon Hellenica 3.4.17; cf. verbatim, Xenophon Agesilaus 1.26). Why, then, does the character Agesilaus seem unconcerned with the historical memorialization of the great deeds that Xenophon says he wishes to inspire? There are a number of possible responses to this question—including that Xenophon’s ethical interests may have guided his presentation of this material. [97] But the Homeric connection noted here invites reflection upon a passage from Pericles’ Funeral Oration in Thucydides that may help to illuminate what Xenophon is doing:

καὶ οὐδὲν προσδεόμενοι οὔτε Ὁμήρου ἐπαινέτου οὔτε ὅστις ἔπεσι μὲν τὸ αὐτίκα τέρψει, τῶν δ’ ἔργων τὴν ὑπόνοιαν ἡ ἀλήθεια βλάψει, ἀλλὰ πᾶσαν μὲν θάλασσαν καὶ γῆν ἐσβατὸν τῇ ἡμετέρᾳ τόλμῃ καταναγκάσαντες γενέσθαι, πανταχοῦ δὲ μνημεῖα κακῶν τε κἀγαθῶν ἀίδια ξυγκατοικίσαντες.

We have no requirement to be the object of Homer’s tribute, nor that of any other who will provide fleeting pleasure through his words, but to whose version of events the truth will do injury. We have forced the whole sea and earth to be open to our boldness, and have sowed everywhere eternal monuments to both our vengeance and our benefactions.

Thucydides 2.41.4


The Funeral Oration, of course, emphasizes throughout, as here, the tension between logos and ergon. [
98] But in its surface rejection of Homeric poetry and its emphasis on the creation of memory through action, this passage also offers a way of thinking about Xenophon’s characterization of Agesilaus. The deeds of the deceased and the achievements of the polis are here converted into memory through words, not once, but twice—once by the ostensible speaker, Pericles, and once by Thucydides, the historian. Encomium is therefore acknowledged both implicitly and explicitly within the text as one of the new ‘tools of memory.’

An important passage in this regard is the controversy over whether the remains of the Ten Thousand should found a colony. The idea begins in Xenophon’s own mind and expands outward through rumor until it becomes the subject of a military assembly, climaxing in a defensive speech by Xenophon himself. At issue are both the possibility of the soldiers settling in a new land far from their homes and the rewards that might accrue to Xenophon as a result. The quasi-heroic position of κτίστης is on offer, but so are immediate power and access to wealth.

The colony-idea is first raised in Xenophon’s mind late in Book 5 of the Anabasis:

ἐν δὲ τούτῳ τῷ χρόνῳ Ξενοφῶντι, ὁρῶντι μὲν ὁπλίτας πολλοὺς τῶν Ἑλλήνων, ὁρῶντι δὲ πελταστὰς πολλοὺς καὶ τοξότας καὶ σφενδονήτας καὶ ἱππέας δὲ καὶ μάλα ἤδη διὰ τὴν τριβὴν ἱκανούς, ὄντας δ’ ἐν τῷ Πόντῳ, ἔνθα οὐκ ἂν ἀπ’ ὀλίγων χρημάτων τοσαύτη δύναμις παρεσκευάσθη, καλὸν αὐτῷ ἐδόκει εἶναι χώραν καὶ δύναμιν τῇ Ἑλλάδι προσκτήσασθαι πόλιν κατοικίσαντας. καὶ γενέσθαι ἂν αὐτῷ ἐδόκει μεγάλη, καταλογιζομένῳ τό τε αὑτῶν πλῆθος καὶ τοὺς περιοικοῦντας τὸν Πόντον. καὶ ἐπὶ τούτοις ἐθύετο πρίν τινι εἰπεῖν τῶν στρατιωτῶν Σιλανὸν παρακαλέσας τὸν Κύρου μάντιν γενόμενον τὸν Ἀμπρακιώτην. {281|282}

To Xenophon at that moment, as he looked upon the large numbers of Greek infantry, light-armed troops, archers, slingers, and cavalry—especially because they were at the ready due to their experience—present in Pontus, where such a vast military force would have been otherwise readied only at significant expense, it seemed that it would be a good idea for them to acquire land and influence for Greece by settling a city. And it seemed to him that it would be a large one, as he calculated their own numbers along with those who lived in the surrounding region of Pontus. And so, before saying anything to any one of the soldiers, he sacrificed towards these goals, after sending for Silanus the Ambraciot, formerly the prophet of Cyrus.

Xenophon Anabasis 5.6.15–16


Clustered within this passage is the vocabulary of colonial foundation (χώραν, gaining significance by association; προσκτήσασθαι; κατοικίσαντας), and even a potential oblique connection to the traditional preparatory rituals, in the reference to sacrifice (ἐθύετο). The precise context and purpose of this particular sacrifice, however, are deliberately misrepresented by Timasion and perhaps even misconstrued by Xenophon’s own men. [
102] The problem suggests that the reader, too, may not be out of bounds in expecting for a moment that this sacrifice is intended as a prologue to the usual foundation rites, particularly given the word order of the sentence, which mentions the ritual before indicating its audience.

Following this scene, the colony idea is deconstructed almost immediately by Silanus the mantis. The rumor he spreads amongst the men is presented in terms that echo—but alter—Xenophon’s initial thoughts (Xenophon Anabasis 5.6.17). Silanus repeats the general concept, but changes Xenophon’s motivations from apparently altruistic and ‘panhellenic’ ones to selfish ones. While the character Xenophon was shown contemplating the future and assessing the resources of the potential colony, Silanus instead implies more immediate concerns about personal acclaim. The central issue for the men becomes not the foundation of a potentially great city, but simply the question of whether to remain where they are now: Xenophon’s motivations are minimized in the face of the soldiers’ concern for their own fate (Xenophon Anabasis 5.6.19). Timasion and Thorax reduce the issue once again in their report to the local merchants (Xenophon Anabasis 5.6.19-20), focusing upon whether or not the army may put pressure upon them by taking up permanent residence. The idea of the colony {282|283} has now drifted far away: when it is recollected by the Achaeans Philesias and Lycon, it is depicted as a private rumor started by Xenophon himself, accompanied by secret machinations (Xenophon Anabasis 5.6.27). Xenophon capitulates and abandons his plans (Xenophon Anabasis 5.6.28–31).

When the colony idea is first introduced in the report of Xenophon’s thoughts, it is presented in terms that tend towards the general, the ennobling, and the eternal. However, as it is debated and gradually dismissed, the emphasis moves to immediate benefits and liabilities, and finally to shallow motivations and open distrust. The implication here seems to be that Xenophon the character is able to conceive of himself as a κτίστης, but his men are irrevocably focused on baser, more transient concerns. Xenophon the writer is therefore here able to ennoble Xenophon the character in two ways: firstly, through the contemplation of the image of the colonial founder, regardless of whether that image is actually activated; and secondly, through the character’s ‘selfless’ inclination to yield to the wishes of his men (see especially Xenophon Anabasis 5.6.28). And it is, ironically, in this final rejection of the potential honor that the character Xenophon can imitate Agesilaus—having already demonstrated that he knows full well what he is giving up.

5. Conclusion

In fourth-century Greece, a highly developed vocabulary of commemoration permits appropriately positioned individuals both to script (in literature and in the epigraphical record) and to stage (in public works of art) their own historical significance. By making careful choices about their own activities and behaviors, by demonstrating receptivity to acknowledgements offered by others, and even by deliberately memorializing themselves, such individuals demonstrate their conscious ability to harness public discourse to their advantage, both during their lives and after their deaths.

Bibliography

Ajootian, A. 1998. “A Day at the Races: The Tyrannicides in the Fifth-Century Agora.” In Hartswick and Sturgeon 1998:1–13.

Anderson, J. K. 1963. “The Statue of Chabrias.” American Journal of Archaeology 67:411–413.

Baragwanath, E. 2008. Motivation and Narrative in Herodotus. Oxford.

Bergmann, B., and C. Kondoleon, eds. 1999. The Art of Ancient Spectacle. Studies in the History of Art 56. Center for Advanced Study in the Visual Arts Symposium Papers 34. New Haven.

Blackwell, C. W. 2003. “An Introduction to the Athenian Democracy.” In Lanni 2003. Republished as “Athenian Democracy: A Brief Overview,” in Dēmos: Classical Athenian Democracy, http://www.stoa.org/projects/demos/article_democracy_overview?page=1&greekEncoding=UnicodeC. Project of The Stoa: A Consortium for Electronic Publication in the Humanities.

Bommelaer, J-F., and D. de Didier Laroche. 1991. Guide de Delphes: Le Site. Paris.

Breitenbach, H. R. 1967. “Xenophon von Athen.” RE IX A2:1567–1910.

Brunnsåker, S. 1971. The Tyrant-Slayers of Kritios and Nesiotes: A Critical Study of the Sources and Restorations. Stockholm.

Buckler, J., and H. Beck. 2008. Central Greece and the Politics of Power in the Fourth Century BC. Cambridge.

Burnett, A. P., and C. N. Edmonson. 1961. “The Chabrias Monument in the Athenian Agora.” Hesperia 30:74–91.

Carlier, P., ed. 1996. Le IVe siècle av. J.-C.: Approches historiographiques. Paris.

Cartledge, P. 1987. Agesilaos and the Crisis of Sparta. Baltimore.

Cawkwell, G. 2004. “When, How, and Why Did Xenophon Write the Anabasis?” In Fox 2004:47–67.

Clairmont, C. W. 1983. Patrios nomos: Public Burial in Athens during the Fifth and Fourth Centuries BC. 2 vols. Oxford.

Clarke, M. J. et al., eds. 2006. Epic Interactions: Perspectives on Homer, Virgil, and the Epic Tradition Presented to Jasper Griffin by Former Pupils. Oxford.

Connor, W. R. 1987. “Tribes, Festivals, and Processions: Civic Ceremonial and Political Manipulation in Archaic Greece.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 107:40–50.

Crane, G. 1996. The Blinded Eye: Thucydides and the New Written Word. Lanham, MD.

Currie, B. 2002. “Euthymos of Locri: A Case Study in Heroization in the Classical Period.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 122:24–44.

Davies, J. K. 1996. “Documents and ‘Documents’ in Fourth-Century Historiography.” In Carlier 1996:29–39.

Day, J. W. 1994. “Interactive Offerings: Early Greek Dedicatory Epigrams and Ritual.” Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 96:37–74.

———. 1989. “Rituals in Stone: Early Greek Grave Epigrams and Monuments.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 109:16–28.

Derderian, K. 2001. Leaving Words to Remember: Greek Mourning and the Advent of Literacy. Leiden.

Dewald, C. 1987. “Narrative Surface and Authorial Voice in Herodotus’ Histories.” Arethusa 20:147–170.

Dewald, C., and J. Marincola, eds. 2006. The Cambridge Companion to Herodotus. Cambridge.

Dillery, J. 1995. Xenophon and the History of His Times. London.

Easterling, P. E., and B. M. W. Knox, eds. 1989. The Cambridge History of Classical Literature. Vol. I, Greek Literature. Part 1, Early Greek Poetry. Cambridge.

Ferrario, S. 2006a. “Replaying Antigone: Changing Patterns of Public and Private Commemoration at Athens c. 440–350.” In Patterson 2006:79–117.

———. 2006b Towards the ‘Great Man’: Individuals and Groups as Agents of Historical Change in Classical Greece. PhD diss., Princeton.

Flower, M. 1988. “Agesilaus of Sparta and the Origins of the Ruler Cult.” Classical Quarterly 38:123–134.

Flower, M. 1994. Theopompus of Chios: History and Rhetoric in the Fourth Century BC. Oxford.

Fox, R. L., ed. 2004. The Long March: Xenophon and the Ten Thousand. New Haven.

Gerolymatos, A. 1985. “Fourth Century Boeotian Use of the Proxenia in International Relations.” In Roesch and Argoud 1985:307–309.

Gygax, M. D. 2006. “Plutarch on Alcibiades’ Return to Athens.” Mnemosyne 59:481–500.

Harley, T. R. 1942. “A Greater Than Leonidas.” Greece and Rome 11:68–83.

Hanson, V. D., ed. 1991. Hoplites: The Classical Greek Battle Experience. London.

Hartswick, K. J., and M. C. Sturgeon, eds. 1998. ΣΤΕΦΑΝΟΣ: Studies in Honor of Brunilde Sismondo Ridgway. Philadelphia.

Hedrick, C. 1999. “Democracy and the Athenian Epigraphical Habit.” Hesperia 68:387–439.

Henry, A. S. 1983. Honours and Privileges in Athenian Decrees: The Principal Formulae of Athenian Honorary Decrees. Subsidia epigraphica 10. Hildescheim.

von Hesberg, H. 1999. “The King on Stage.” In Bergmann and Kondoleon 1999:65–75.

Hornblower, S. 2002. The Greek World, 479–323 BC. London.

Jackson, A. H. 1991. “Hoplites and the Gods: The Dedication of Captured Arms and Armour.” In Hanson 1991:228–249.

Jacoby, F. 1945. “Some Athenian Epigrams from the Persian Wars.” Hesperia 14:157–211.

Kearns, E. 1989. The Heroes of Attica. Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies Suppl. 57. London.

Keesling, C. M. 2003. The Votive Statues of the Athenian Acropolis. Cambridge.

Kowalzig, B. 2004. “Changing Choral Worlds: Song-Dance and Society in Athens and Beyond.” In Murray and Wilson 2004:39–65.

Kurke, L. 1991. The Traffic in Praise: Pindar and the Poetics of Social Economy. Ithaca.

Kuttner, A. 1999. “Hellenistic Images of Spectacle from Alexander to Augustus.” In Bergmann and Kondoleon 1999:97–123.

Lanni, A., ed. 2003. Athenian Law in its Democratic Context. Center for Hellenic Studies Online Discussion Series. http://chs.harvard.edu/cgi-bin/WebObjects/workbench.woa/wa/pageR?tn=ArticleWrapper&bdc=12&mn=1184.

Lawton, C. L. 1995. Attic Document Reliefs: Art and Politics in Ancient Athens. Oxford.

Loraux, N. 1981. L’invention d’Athènes: histoire de l’oraison funèbre dans la ‘cité classique’. Paris. Also pub. as The Invention of Athens: The Funeral Oration in the Classical City, trans. A. Sheridan. Cambridge, MA, 1986.

Luraghi, N. 2006. “Meta-historiê: Method and Genre in the Histories.” In Dewald and Marincola 2006:76–91.

MacMullen, R. 1982. “The Epigraphic Habit in the Roman Empire.” American Journal of Philology 103:233–246.

Marchant, E. C., ed. 1925. Xenophon: Scripta Minora. London.

McCauley, B. A. 1993. Hero Cults and Politics in Fifth Century Greece. PhD diss., University of Iowa.

Meiggs, R., and D. Lewis, eds. 1969. A Selection of Greek Historical Inscriptions to the End of the Fifth Century BC. Oxford.

Meritt, B. D. 1936. “Greek Inscriptions.” Hesperia 5.3 (The American Excavations in the Athenian Agora: Tenth Report):355–430.

Mitchell, L. G. 1997. Greeks Bearing Gifts: The Public Use of Private Relationships in the Greek World, 435–323 BC. Cambridge.

Momigliano, A. 1972. “Tradition and the Classical Historian.” History and Theory 11:279–293.

Murray, O. 1993. Early Greece. 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA.

Murray, P., and P. Wilson, eds. 2004. Music and The Muses: The Culture of ‘Mousike’ in the Classical Athenian City. Oxford.

Ober, J., and C. Hedrick, eds. 1996. Dêmokratia: A Conversation on Democracies, Ancient and Modern. Princeton.

Osborne, R. 1996. Greece in the Making, 1200–479 BC. London.

Page, D. L., ed. 1962. Poetae melici Graeci. Oxford.

———, ed. 1981. Further Greek Epigrams. Cambridge.

Patterson, C., ed. 2006. Antigone’s Answer: Essays on Death and Burial, Family and State in Classical Athens. Special Issue, Helios 33.

Pelling, C. 2006. “Homer and Herodotus.” In M. J. Clarke et al. 2006:75–104.

Perlman, S. 1968. “Athenian Democracy and the Revival of Imperialistic Expansion at the Beginning of the Fourth Century BC.” Classical Philology 63:257–267.

———. 1958. “A Note on the Political Implications of Proxenia in the Fourth Century BC.” Classical Quarterly 8:185–191.

Pfohl, G., ed. 1967. Greek Poems on Stones. Vol. 1, Epitaphs from the Seventh to the Fifth Centuries BC. Leiden.

Pownall, F. 2004. Lessons from the Past: The Moral Use of History in Fourth-Century Prose. Ann Arbor.

Prasad, P. H. 2007. “A Comparative Analysis of Pindar’s Victory Odes and Vedic Poetry, with a Commentary on Olympian 1.” Unpublished paper. Washington, DC.

Raaflaub, K. A. 1996. “Equalities and Inequalities in Athenian Democracy.” In Ober and Hedrick 1996:139–174.

Race, W. H. 1987. “Pindaric Encomium and Isokrates’ Evagoras.” Transactions of the American Philological Association 117:131–155.

Raubitschek, A. E. 1940. “Two Monuments Erected after the Victory of Marathon.” American Journal of Archaeology 44:53–59.

Rhodes, P. J., and R. Osborne, eds. 2007. Greek Historical Inscriptions, 404323 BC. Oxford.

Robertson, N. 1976. “False Documents at Athens: Fifth Century History and Fourth Century Publicists.” Historical Reflections 3:3–25.

Roesch, P., and G. Argoud, eds. 1985. La Béotie antique: Lyon, Saint-Etienne, 16–20 mai 1983. Paris.

Roisman, J., ed. 2003. Brill’s Companion to Alexander the Great. Leiden.

Rood, T. 2004. “Panhellenism and Self-Presentation: Xenophon’s Speeches.” In Fox 2004:305–329.

Rose, H. J. 1957. Review of Gottmenschentum und griechische Städte, by C. Habicht, 1956. Journal of Hellenic Studies 77.2:340–341.

Samons, L. J., II. 2004. What’s Wrong with Democracy? From Athenian Practice to American Worship. Berkeley.

Seager, R. 1967. “Thrasybulus, Conon and Athenian Imperialism, 396-386 BC.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 87:95–115.

Segal, C. 1989. “Pindar.” In Easterling and Knox 1989:185–194.

Shrimpton, G. S. 1997. History and Memory in Ancient Greece. Montreal.

———. 1971. “The Theban Supremacy in Fourth-Century Literature.” Phoenix 25:310–318.

Shur, E. G. 1931. Sculptured Portraits of Greek Statesmen. Baltimore.

Starr, C. 1968. The Awakening of the Greek Historical Spirit. New York.

Stewart, A. 2003. “Alexander in Greek and Roman Art.” In Roisman 2003:31–66.

———. 1993. Faces of Power: Alexander’s Image and Hellenistic Politics. Berkeley.

Strauss, B. S. 1984. “Thrasybulus and Conon: A Rivalry in Athens in the 390s B.C.” American Journal of Philology 105:37–48.

Taylor, M. W. 1981. The Tyrant Slayers: The Heroic Image in Fifth Century BC Athenian Art and Politics. New York.

Thomas, R. 1989. Oral Tradition and Written Record in Classical Athens. Cambridge.

Tod, M. N. 1948. A Selection of Greek Historical Inscriptions. Vol. II, From 403 to 323 BC. Oxford.

———. 1946. A Selection of Greek Historical Inscriptions. Vol I, To the End of the Fifth Century BC. 2nd ed. Oxford.

Umholtz, G. 2002. “Architraval Arrogance? Dedicatory Inscriptions in Greek Architecture of the Classical Period.” Hesperia 71:261–293.

Vatin, C. 1991. Monuments votifs de Delphes. Archaeologia Perusina 10. Rome.

Walbank, M. B. 1978. Athenian Proxenies of the Fifth Century BC. Toronto.

West, William C., III. 1969. “The Trophies of the Persian Wars.” Classical Philology 64:7–19.

Zanker, P. 1988. The Power of Images in the Age of Augustus. Trans. A. Shapiro. Ann Arbor.

Footnotes

[ back ] 1. Iliad 9.412–416; cf. below.

[ back ] 2. See Stewart 1993:229–340.

[ back ] 3. E.g. Zanker 1988.

[ back ] 4. Iliad 6.357–358; cf. below.

[ back ] 5. All dates in this chapter are BCE. All translations are my own unless otherwise noted.

[ back ] 6. Starr 1968 traces the evolution of this concept, in the form of an “intellectual history of early Greece” (5), from the time of the Homeric poems through the fifth century; see also Derderian 2001, esp. 161–188.

[ back ] 7. On the essence of this concept as ‘historical’ in classical Greece, see Momigliano 1972, esp. 283–284, 290.

[ back ] 8. M. Flower, critical correspondence of 4–30–06; Starr 1968, esp. 12–23, 91–96.

[ back ] 9. On the evolving relationship between memory and historical context during the fifth century, see Derderian 2001, esp. 102–111, 161–188, 192–194. Both this discussion and Starr’s (see n10, below) have been very influential upon my thinking about the issues discussed here.

[ back ] 10. On Pindar as a potential bridge between heroism and history, see Starr 1968:124–130.

[ back ] 11. Kurke 1991, esp. 163–224; Starr 1968:124–130. I am grateful to P. Hari Prasad for discussion of Pindaric issues in conversation and in class presentation that made the points expressed here increasingly clear and significant to me.

[ back ] 12. See Segal 1989 and Prasad 2007:4–5, both of whose articulations influenced my discussion of the ‘Pindaric world’ here.

[ back ] 13. Kurke 1991, esp. 163–94.

[ back ] 14. On the Antenor group, see Taylor 1981:33–37; on the unique position of these statues in Athenian artistic and political history, see also Keesling 2003:174–176, esp. n25, and Ajootian 1998:1, esp. n4. The most important ancient testimonia cited by these and other analyses are Aristotle Rhetoric 1.9.1368a and Demosthenes 20.70, but a fuller survey of the literary and epigraphical evidence for both statue groups may be found in Brunnsåker 1971.

[ back ] 15. Texts: Page 1962:474–475 nos. 893–896.

[ back ] 16. See n55, below, and Derderian 2001:109–110.

[ back ] 17. During the mid-fifth century, these more elaborate, historically contextualized epitaphs, exceedingly rare in the archaeological record in any case, seem generally to have been confined to foreign benefactors. The two best-known examples from this time are probably the epitaphs of Pythagoras of Selymbria (IG I3 1154, ca. 460–450) and Pythion of Megara (IG I3 1353, ca. 446/5). From the later fifth century, when metrical epitaphs for Athenian citizens are slightly more common in the epigraphical record, see e.g. the epitaphs of Glauciades and -ULOS [sic], discussed in Ferrario 2006a:91–95.

[ back ] 18. See Ferrario 2006a:87–88.

[ back ] 19. As noted in Ferrario 2006a:87n29, approximately 16 proxenies of Athens are attested before 450, and 78 (of which 68 are referenced in extant inscriptions) from the years 450–400 (Walbank 1978:ix–xiv). On the first appearance of honors for Athenian citizens in the archaeological record (as opposed to the literary testimonia), see e.g. Henry 1983:13, 22–23; on proxenoi in the Attic document reliefs, see Lawton 1995, esp. 32.

[ back ] 20. Hedrick 1999:391–392.

[ back ] 21. Ferrario 2006a:96–97.

[ back ] 22. Thomas 1989:49–53.

[ back ] 23. E.g. Thomas 1989:83–94; Robertson 1976. For a brief history of scholarship on this issue and a methodological discussion, see Davies 1996.

[ back ] 24. E.g. Henry 1983:116–162; Walbank 1978. Perlman 1958 briefly treats the use of proxeny outside of Athens (including in Boeotia, op. cit. 189–190); for more on Boeotian proxenies (holding that they seem to have borne much resemblance to Athenian practices, which may have provided their political models), see Gerolymatos 1985. Proxenies and other honors could be hereditary, too, offering a real-life parallel to the endurance of the inscription that recorded the privileges: see Henry 1983:137–140; Perlman 1958:187–188.

[ back ] 25. See Umholtz 2002, who holds that the surviving dedicatory inscriptions of the fourth century, while more numerous than those of previous periods, represent continuity with the past rather than an abrupt change.

[ back ] 26. Keesling 2003:167.

[ back ] 27. Keesling 2003:170–185.

[ back ] 28. See esp. Demosthenes 23.198; Burnett and Edmonson 1961:89. West 1969:14 and nn35–36, with references, notes that by the fourth century, “generals, not the army as a whole, are given credit for setting [trophies] up after a victory.” Keesling 2003:175 holds that athletic victors were part of the narrow class of individuals whose self-representation in sanctuaries had been acceptable prior to the changes evident at this time.

[ back ] 29. Blackwell 2003, accessed 11–29–07.

[ back ] 30. On “qualifications for citizenship” (author’s heading) and for the various governmental and military positions in classical Athens, e.g. Samons 2004:45–49, with both ancient and modern references; see also Raaflaub 1996:154–159. The ephebate, once it became a recognized institution, may or may not have been open to the poorest individuals: see Samons 2004:47n26 and Raaflaub 1996:157.

[ back ] 31. See Keesling in n28, above.

[ back ] 32. Alcibiades is notably defensive in any case: see his speech at Thucydides 6.16.1–3, and cf. Nicias’ attack at 6.12.2.

[ back ] 33. On inter-state relationships, both personal and political, between Greek elites during the later classical era, see Mitchell 1997.

[ back ] 34. Demosthenes 20.69–70, cited and summarized by Keesling 2003:176; see also Burnett and Edmonson 1961:89.

[ back ] 35. Perlman 1968:261nn32–33, 262–263nn45–46 (with references).

[ back ] 36. Strauss 1984:38.

[ back ] 37. Strauss 1984:39–40, with references.

[ back ] 38. The ironic fact that Conon was essentially under contract to the Persians seems to have posed little or no difficulty: see Perlman 1968:262 and n9, citing Xenophon Hellenica 4.8.9 and Diodorus 14.85.2.

[ back ] 39. E.g. Nicias’ famous festal benefactions at Delos (Plutarch Nicias 3.4–6), and Alcibiades’ celebration of the procession for the Eleusinian Mysteries upon his return to Athens from exile (Xenophon Hellenica 1.4.20; Plutarch Alcibiades 34.4).

[ back ] 40. On this general concept, see e.g. Umholtz 2002:278–282, esp. 281n78.

[ back ] 41. See Seager 1967:103.

[ back ] 42. This in spite of the fact that the reconstruction was begun prior to Conon’s intervention: see Seager 1967:103.

[ back ] 43. Burnett and Edmonson 1961:89, with references.

[ back ] 44. Burnett and Edmonson 1961:89 and passim.

[ back ] 45. Burnett and Edmonson 1961:89, citing Diodorus 15.33.4 and Nepos Chabrias 1.3.

[ back ] 46. Anderson 1963:412–413.

[ back ] 47. Burnett and Edmonson 1961:89 and n43, citing Demosthenes 24.180.

[ back ] 48. Shrimpton 1971.

[ back ] 49. E.g. Buckler and Beck 2008:12–15 (with cross-references), 133–139.

[ back ] 50. Hedrick 1999 uses this phrase for his title, explaining that it has been borrowed from MacMullen 1982.

[ back ] 51. Shrimpton 1971:313 discusses the Leuctra inscription, along with the Delphi Pelopidas statue base, for slightly different reasons, noting: “Fortunately, we do possess some inscriptional proof of the prestige being won by the Theban heroes in central Greece while they were being ignored in Athens . . . We must conclude, then, that very shortly after the actual events there existed glowing stories of Pelopidas and Epaminondas (whether literary or oral) waiting to enter Athenian literary traditions from central Greece.”

[ back ] 52. Tod 1948:93–94n130, with ancient references.

[ back ] 53. Tod 1948:93 suggests that the last line “might be interpreted as a veiled protest against the undue glorification of [Epaminondas],” although Rhodes and Osborne 2007:151 disagree.

[ back ] 54. E.g. the entries in Pfohl 1967.

[ back ] 55. Cf. n16, above. Tyrannicide base epigram: Meritt 1936:355–358 (edition); Page 1981:188 et al. Persian War epigrams: bibliography collected at IG I3 503/504 (edition); Clairmont 1983:106–111; Meiggs and Lewis 1969:54–57 no. 26; cf. also Jacoby 1945:161nn19–20 and passim for extensive references to earlier discussions.

[ back ] 56. See Derderian 2001, esp. the detailed treatment of Homeric and other poetical resonances in the Persian War epigrams at 102–103; Day 1989; cf. also Day 1994.

[ back ] 57. The Pindaric quality of this poetry is mentioned (but not explored in detail) by Rhodes and Osborne 2007:150.

[ back ] 58. See n28, above, and Aeschines 3.177–191.

[ back ] 59. See n51, above.

[ back ] 60. E.g. Herodotus on the colonization narratives of Cyrene (Herodotus 4.150–159), and Thucydides on the colonization narrative of Sicily (Thucydides 6.2.1–5.3). This brief summary of the role of the κτίστης is based upon the points iterated by Osborne 1996:8–17, 115–129, 202–207, 232–242; and Murray 1993:102–123.

[ back ] 61. Cited by Taylor 1981:20–21; cf. also Kearns 1989:55, 150.

[ back ] 62. Currie 2002:37, emphasis original.

[ back ] 63. Currie 2002:26, 36–38, 43; cf. also Currie’s discussion of Connor’s analysis of a somewhat similar pattern from the archaic period: Currie 2002:39, citing Connor 1987.

[ back ] 64. McCauley 1993:244n596 notes the suggestion in Cartledge 1987:85 that Brasidas’ experiences anticipate Lysander’s.

[ back ] 65. E.g. Thucydides 4.11.4, 81.1–2, 112.1–2, 5.10.6, et al.; see also Harley 1942:68–83. I am grateful to S. Saporito for discussion of Brasidas in conversation and in class presentation that called my attention to and helped to shape my interpretations of some of the material that I treat here.

[ back ] 66. Thucydides 5.11.1.

[ back ] 67. Thucydides 4.102.3.

[ back ] 68. See Currie 2002:37–38, esp. n134; cf. also McCauley 1993:243. I do not necessarily agree that the Thucydidean passage implies a wholesale transfer of honors from Hagnon to Brasidas; the emphasis appears to be upon the rituals established for the new κτίστης, rather than upon those existing for the old one.

[ back ] 69. Henry 1983:22–23 demonstrates that inscriptions recording the award of golden crowns are exceptionally rare in the fifth and earlier fourth centuries. On literary testimonia and other evidence for such crowns, see e.g. Gygax 2006, esp. 490–496.

[ back ] 70. ἰδίᾳ δὲ ἐταινίουν τε καὶ προσήρχοντο ὥσπερ ἀθλητῇ, “individually they placed bands upon his head and presented him accolades as if for an athletic champion” (Thucydides 4.121.1).

[ back ] 71. Currie 2002, esp. 37n133, 43. I am grateful to M. Flower for the recommendation some time ago that I expand this study to include Lysander (especially his ‘Nauarch’s Monument’ at Delphi) and other non-Athenians.

[ back ] 72. Plutarch Lysander 18.3–4, cited by Flower 1988:128 and n21, who notes that Plutarch explicitly references Duris of Samos on this subject; if the reference is acceptable at face value, then the literary evidence for this cult may be not only locally grounded but also much closer in time to the actual events (Flower 1988:132).

[ back ] 73. Jackson 1991, esp. 230.

[ back ] 74. At Delphi, the most famous named examples from the archaic period are probably Croesus (see Herodotus 1.50.1–55.1) and the Alcmaeonids, who restored the Temple of Apollo after a fire in 548/7 BCE (the Alcmaeonid marble façade on that temple is dated to 514–505: see Bommelaer and Laroche 1991:20).

[ back ] 75. The Spartan general Pausanias, victor of Plataea, was forbidden to memorialize himself by name on the collective Greek monument to the Persian Wars at Delphi (Thucydides 1.132.2–3), and both the Miltiades statue group there (Pausanias 10.10.1–2; Bommelaer and Laroche 1991:110–111, with additional references) and the Callimachus monument on the Athenian Acropolis (Raubitschek 1940:53–56) seem to have been posthumous.

[ back ] 76. Plutarch Lysander 18.1; Pausanias 10.9.7–10. For a summary of the monument, see Bommelaer and Laroche 1991:108–109; on the problems of its reconstruction, see Vatin 1991:103–138; for the inscriptions on the statue bases, see Meiggs and Lewis 1969:287–290 no. 95 and Tod 1946:228–231 nos. 94–95; for an analysis of the potential impact of Lysander’s monument in its historical and physical context, see Crane 1996:177–179, 205–206 (making the comparison with Pausanias).

[ back ] 77. Lawton 1995:31–32.

[ back ] 78. Hornblower 2002:183; Shur 1931:31.

[ back ] 79. Crane 1996:177.

[ back ] 80. On the evolution of the civic function of mousikê from the archaic into the classical era at Athens, see Kowalzig 2004; cf. Murray and Wilson 2004:3.

[ back ] 81. Crane 1996:177.

[ back ] 82. Flower 1988:132.

[ back ] 83. See the discussion by Flower 1988:132–133, with references. Rose’s understanding of C. Habicht’s argument provides additional insight (see Rose 1957:340): “[Habicht] holds, rightly as I believe, that the institution of worship of any human being has nothing to do with his character, but is invariably, in the case of the Greek cities, a response to some one specific act resulting in great benefit to the community in question, such as deliverance from a dangerous enemy, restoration of its constitution after a period of tyranny or foreign domination, or the like.”

[ back ] 84. McCauley 1993:245–248, 257–260 sees the escalation of heroic honors, especially in the course of the fifth century, as pointing towards Lysander’s reception (“It was already apparent in the time of Lysander that if athletes and other generals could become heroes, then the only thing left for an outstanding individual to do was to become a god,” 260), but also notes the other side of the transaction, citing (245–246) ancient perceptions that Lysander was a conscious manipulator of religious symbolism.

[ back ] 85. Flower 1988:133.

[ back ] 86. McCauley 1993:247–248.

[ back ] 87. Flower 1988:133–134.

[ back ] 88. Luraghi 2006, esp. 87.

[ back ] 89. See n11, above.

[ back ] 90. For other analyses of this echo, e.g. Baragwanath 2008:68–70 and nn41–42; Pelling 2006:93–94 and n51. On Herodotus’ deliberate establishment of interactions between the “authorial voice” of the historian and the content of the text, see Dewald 1987, esp. 153.

[ back ] 91. On literacy as a means for the construction of memory, see Shrimpton 1997:48–72, 88–91, 186–190; Thomas 1989, esp. 118–154; cf. also Derderian 2001, esp. 63–113.

[ back ] 92. Flower 1988:128 and passim.

[ back ] 93. Xenophon Hellenica 3.4.7–10 (Lysander), 4.1.1–2, 41 (Persian Empire), 4.2.3 (recall), 4.3.9 (cavalry battle, with Agesilaus setting up a trophy afterwards).

[ back ] 94. Xenophon Agesilaus 11.7; Plutarch Agesilaus 2.2, both sources are cited by Flower 1988:127, who also mentions this story. On the (spurious) tradition of Alexander’s artistic ‘edict’ upon his own image, see the references collected by Stewart 1993:360–362; see also Stewart 2003:32.

[ back ] 95. Respectively, Xenophon Hellenica 4.2.2–3; Xenophon Agesilaus 1.36.

[ back ] 96. Xenophon Hellenica 3.4.16–18; cf. Iliad 18.483–608 (shield), 23.257–897 (funeral games).

[ back ] 97. An important formulation of Xenophon’s interest in leadership paradigms is Breitenbach 1967; see also Dillery 1995.

[ back ] 98. My reading of this passage is indebted to the interpretation of the epitaphios logos as an agonistic and historically contextualized genre by Derderian 2001, esp. 163–178, 182–185 (the latter specifically on the logos-ergon dichotomy); cf. also, as Derderian does, Loraux 1981.

[ back ] 99. For a summary of the ancient sources, see Marchant 1925: intro. xvii–xx; for more information, see Flower 1994:149–150.

[ back ] 100. See Pownall 2004:32–35 on the relationship between Xenophon’s Agesilaus and Isocrates’ Evagoras, referring on this topic (32n125) to Race 1987.

[ back ] 101. While this suggestion might be used to bolster the interpretation of the Anabasis as an apologetic work (recently on this issue, e.g. Rood 2004:322–326; and cf., in the same collection, Cawkwell 2004), I am not here attempting to engage with this particular problem.

[ back ] 102. Xenophon Anabasis 5.6.22 and 27, respectively.

[ back ] 103. E.g. the surveys by von Hesberg 1999 and Kuttner 1999.

[ back ] 104. Some of this material, particularly in section 2, first appeared in my dissertation (Ferrario 2006b), and I remain very grateful to the organizers, Nino Luraghi and Riccardo Vattuone, and to the other Bologna conference participants for the opportunity to explore these ideas in new ways. I would also like to thank Giovanni Parmeggiani for his editorial work and support.