Poetry as Initiation: The Center for Hellenic Studies Symposium on the Derveni Papyrus

  Papadopoulou, Ioanna, and Leonard Muellner, eds. 2014. Poetry as Initiation: The Center for Hellenic Studies Symposium on the Derveni Papyrus. Hellenic Studies Series 63. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_PapadopoulouI_MuellnerL_eds.Poetry_as_Initiation.2014.


Chapter 7. Unlocking the Orphic Doors: Interpretation of Poetry in the Derveni Papryus between Presocratics and Alexandrians [1]

Jeffrey Rusten

Cornell University

Prelude: Reader 1: The Owner of the Derveni Papyrus

The urge to attach an author’s name to the Derveni Papyrus is natural for everyone who reads it, which should remind us of why pseudepigrapha were so popular in the ancient world. I have my own preferences, admittedly based not so much on a dispassionate consideration of the evidence as on the reason I was drawn to the papyrus myself, an interest in the forms of ancient literary scholarship. Though I have no specific proposal to make, going over the possible identities, both of its author and of its owner, and how we might argue for and against each one is in itself a useful way of evaluating the evidence we now have: it consists of the archaeological context of the find, the form of the book, the contents of the individual columns, and the quotations not only from Orpheus’ theogony but also from Heraclitus and, I still believe, other authors as well.

But I am one of those who find the contents of most of the papyrus difficult to reconcile with this interpretation of its owner, and so I want to press on to other possible reasons for its inclusion in the grave goods. The collection of texts on books in burials by Wolfgang Speyer (1970), as well as studies of papyrus finds in general, reminds us that books buried with a body have multiple possible meanings. They might be the books written by the entombed—Propertius (2.10.25ff) imagines his funeral attended by no one but the books he has written for his girlfriend, whereas a malicious Horace (Satires 1.10.63–64) points out that Lucilius wrote far too much, so that his body could be completely burnt by his collected works without the need for any additional fuel. The sarcophagus of the Etruscan Laris Pulenas depicts him proudly holding a copy of his treatise on divination (Bonfante 2006), not really comparable with Greek burials but included here because of its religious connection and because it is more or less contemporary with the Derveni Papyrus.

Books in a grave might also be a prized possession of the owner—I know of no literary documentation of this motive, but people reading and holding scrolls was a favorite theme of Attic art, and pride in books seems likely to be behind the placement of a scroll of Timotheus near a wooden sarcophagus in third-century BC Egypt (MP3 1537, Hordern 2002 62–73), as well as luxury copies of Homer (MP3 642), Alcman (MP3 78) and perhaps Bacchylides (MP3 175) found later in burials. The body in Derveni tomb A was a military man, or, at any rate, greaves and a bridle were found among his grave goods. It may seem odd that such a man owned any books at all, but stranger things can be imagined, as in the fragment of the fourth-century comedy by Alexis, in which Linus tries to convince an unlikely pupil, Heracles, that he should develop a passion for books (Alexis, Linus PCG fr. 140):

ΛΙΝ. βιβλίον
ἐντεῦθεν ὅ τι βούλει προσελθὼν γὰρ λαβέ͵
ἔπειτ᾽ ἀναγνώσει͵ πάνυ γε διασκοπῶν
ἀπὸ τῶν ἐπιγραμμάτων ἀτρέμα τε καὶ σχολῇ.
Ὀρφεὺς ἔνεστιν͵ Ἡσίοδος͵ τραγῳδίαι͵ {116|117}
Χοιρίλος͵ Ὅμηρος͵ <ἔστ᾽> Ἐπίχαρμος͵ γράμματα
παντοδαπά. δηλώσεις γὰρ οὕτω τὴν φύσιν͵
ἐπὶ τί μάλισθ’ ὥρμηκε.
ΗΡ. τουτὶ λαμβάνω.
ΛΙΝ. δεῖξον ὅ τι ἐστὶ πρῶτον.
ΗΡ. ὀψαρτυσία͵
ὥς φησι τοὐπίγραμμα.
ΛΙΝ. φιλόσοφός τις εἶ͵
εὔδηλον͵ ὃς παρεὶς τοσαῦτα γράμματα
Σίμου τέχνην ἔλαβες.

Linus: Come up and take
any book you want from here; then,
after looking quite carefully through the titles,
read quietly and at your leisure.
Orpheus is there, and Hesiod, Tragedies,
Choirilus, Homer, there’s Epicharmus, writings
of all kinds, and so you’ll reveal your nature
by what you’re eager for.
Heracles: I’ll take this.
Linus: Show me what it is first.
Heracles: The Joy of Cooking,
according to the title.
Linus: You’re a philosopher,
clearly: you pass by so many other writings
and seize the art of Simus.


Linus offers him Orpheus, Hesiod, tragedy, Homer, and Epicharmus—Choirilus here must be a joke—as the authors from which he can choose, and in line 7 he says “that way you will show what you’re like, your predilection.” When Heracles naturally picks up a cookbook, his flattering teacher doesn’t miss a beat, and praises his philosophical choice.

So for characterizing the owner of the book we have a range of possibilities. Even if he was not the author, but an owner-reader, he was in some sense an addressee of the book; why did he choose to read it? How did he read it? Was he a religious addressee, who needed to be converted and instructed? Or a philosophical addressee, hoping to find confirmation for his cosmogony in specialized interpretation? Or perhaps a reader of literature who wanted some help when reading the theogony of Orpheus? Or was the mere fact of ownership of such a finely produced book his primary aim? {117|118}

Reader 2: The Author of the Derveni Papyrus and His Diverse Interests

For the author of the Derveni Papyrus, our primary evidence is of course the contents of his work, and they are not entirely homogeneous. In Figure 1 I give a conspectus of the total contents of the papyrus, with the column number, the section of the theogony discussed, and the author’s interpretation and any other texts quoted.

Figure 1. Conspectus of the Contents of the Derveni Papyrus.






























Col. Section of Theogony Discussed Commentator’s Interpretation
I ? ?
II ? “Erinyes” mentioned.
III ? “Daimones … servants of the gods” mentioned.
IV ? Heraclitus cited (VS 22 b3, B94) on the Erinyes and the sun (εἰ γάρ τι εὔρους ἑωυτοῦ ἐκβήσεται, Ἐρινύες νιν ἐξευρήσουσι).
V   Oracles and dreams.
VI ? Reasons for offering σπονδαί, χοαί, and πόπανα to the Eumenides.
VII Cf. [Plato], Alcibiades II.147d (below) Orpheus’ poetry is αἰνιγματώδης (cites OF 13, 245.1).
VIII Zeus succeeds Kronos (Orph. fr. 4–5) Verses are in hyperbaton.
IX Zeus succeeds Kronos τὰ ὄντα were placed in disorder and prevented from recombining.
X Oracle of Nyx (Orph. fr. 6) φωνεῖν = λέγειν = διδάσκειν, so that πανομφεύουσαν (epithet of Nyx?) means πάντα διδάσκουσαν.
XI Oracle of Nyx a) ἄδυτον (of Nyx) = the depth (βάθος) of darkness;
b) χρᾶν (“give prophecies”) = ἀρκεῖν “(be sufficient”), with two illustrative quotations (from prose). {118|119}
XII ? “Olympos” is not οὐρανός (εὐρύς), but χρόνος (μακρός).
XIII Zeus hears θέσφατα from Kronos (Orph. fr. 7)
Zeus swallows Phanes (Orph. fr. 8)
a) ? “variant reading” with ἀκούσας rejected?;
b) αἰδοῖον refers to ἥλιος.
XIV List of kings: Ouranos (Orph. fr. 10) a) Kronos is called a child of Helios and Ge because the sun causes τὰ ὄντα to strike against each other (κρούεσθαι);
b) Kronos (= Nous) “robbed Ouranos of his rule” by causing things to stike against each other.
XV List of kings: Kronos–Zeus (Orph. fr. 10) a) the formation of the sun (cf. XXIV);
b) the present state of the kosmos (ἡ νῦν μετάστασις) began with rule of Kronos, who is the same as Zeus.
XVI Creation from Protogonos (Phanes) (Orph. fr. 12–13) What now exists was not created, but a rearrangement of previously existent matter.
XVII “Hymn to Zeus” (Orph. fr. 14) Aer has always existed, but received the name Zeus when the present kosmos took shape; he will retain this name until the previous state returns.
XVIII “Hymn to Zeus” The πνεῦμα in Aer was named by Orpheus Moira (= φρόνησις τοῦ θεοῦ by common usage) before Zeus received his name.
XIX “Hymn to Zeus” (Orph. fr. 3, 31, 243, etc.) a) Zeus (= Aer) is called “everything” because Aer can predominate in everything;
b) Moira (Διὸς φρόνησις) determines past, present, and future.
XX ? Criticism of those who seek knowledge through initiation.
XI Birth of Aphrodite? a) explanation of θόρνη (?);
b) μίσγεσθαι = θόρνυσθαι (“mount”) = ἀφροδισιάζειν, so that Aphrodite (= Zeus, Harmonia, and Peitho) received her name when the present kosmos was mixed together (μιχθέντων). {119|120}
XII Rhea “becomes” Demeter (cf. Orph. fr. 1019) Ge, Meter (= Demeter), Rhea, and Hera are the same (with an illustrative quotation from the Hymns).
XIII Creation of Okeanos (subjugation of Achelôos) (Orph. fr. 16) Okeanos=Zeus=Aer.
XIV Creation of the moon (Orph. fr. 16) a) the moon is round and ἰσομελής;
b) φαίνει refers not to the brightness but to the revelation of the moon’s seasons.
XV   a) composition of sun, moon, and stars out of particles with varied heat and brightness;
b) cross-reference back to previous account of sun’s composition (cf. cols. IV, XV).
XVI Zeus mates with his mother (Orph. fr. 18) to produce a child ἑᾶς = “good” (two parallels in verse); if the poet had intended “his own” he could have written ἑοῖο.

Column VII: The Selection of Orpheus and “Enigmatic License”

It has often been noted that the Derveni author’s reinterpretations of poetry continue a well-attested tradition of tendentious interpretation of Homer by rhapsodes and Sophists (Richardson 1975). But we must not overlook one very original feature of this book: it chooses not Homer to interpret, as did almost all earlier and later allegorists, but “Orpheus.” It is striking that some of the poems ascribed to Orpheus at this time seem not to have been completely distinctive in content, but compete with already-known forms and stories: the Orphic hymn to Demeter with the Homeric one, and the theogony with that of Hesiod. The difference, as Fritz Graf has pointed out in connection with the Demeter poems, is probably that the competing poems by the fictitious authors Orpheus and Musaeus “came into being within two closely related circles of theological-speculative interpretation,” in other words, they appealed especially to those who sought religious significance in their poetry. [4] Thus it is not surprising that it is stated at the outset that Orpheus is “special” (col. VII):

The concept of poetry as riddle is known before this text (Struck 2004:39–50), but I find particularly interesting the variant formulation of the principle in the pseudo-Platonic dialogue Alcibiades II 147D. After his interlocutor has expressed frustration with interpreting a poetic text, Socrates says that in fact the text is consistent: not only this poet but almost all other poets speak in riddles, since poetry is by nature enigmatic, and is not for any chance reader to understand (ἔστιν τε γὰρ φύσει ποιητικὴ ἡ σύμπασα αἰνιγματώδης καὶ οὐ τοῦ προστυχόντος ἀνδρὸς γνωρίσαι). And in addition to its being this way by nature, when poetry is in the hands of a resentful man who doesn’t wish to communicate with us but rather to conceal his wisdom as far as possible, the difficulty of understanding the thing that each poet actually means is stretched to an extreme (ἔτι τε πρὸς τῷ φύσει τοιαύτη εἶναι͵ ὅταν λάβηται ἀνδρὸς φθονεροῦ τε καὶ μὴ βουλομένου ἡμῖν ἐνδείκνυσθαι ἀλλ΄ ἀποκρύπτεσθαι ὅτι μάλιστα τὴν αὑτοῦ σοφίαν͵ ὑπερφυῶς δὴ τὸ χρῆμα ὡς δύσγνωστον φαίνεται͵ ὅτι ποτὲ νοοῦσιν ἕκαστος αὐτῶν). The text that he goes on to interpret is from an improbable source, the Margites: he uses the tactic of word-replacement (not found in the Derveni author) to alter the meaning of the line of the Margites to say not that Margites knew everything badly—since to know something badly would be unacceptable to Socrates—but that it was bad for him to know all the trivial things he did know. Certainly this broad statement of principle applied to an unlikely poetic text is not meant to be taken seriously—it seems rather to be a parody of such literary interpretations, like Tiresias’ linguistic reinterpretation of the birth of Dionysus in Euripides’ Bacchae 286–296, or like the Platonic Menexenus, which often seems to parody the institution of the funeral oration. And yet, though Socrates is less than generous in the motives he ascribes to his allegorical poet, he claims the same enigmatic license that the Derveni author does in column VII. {122|123}

Identification/Equivalence as Interpretative Tool

Nor is his second category of identification new: etymological interpretation of gods’ names such as Kronos and Demeter is known of course from Plato’s Cratylus and elsewhere. Heraclitus famously said that Dionysus and Hades were the same, but like many of his formulations this was surprising, complex, based partly on the sound similarity of aidoia, aidôs, and aides, [11] and above all expressed concisely. The Derveni interpreter runs this principle into the ground, in more than a third of the columns postulating, usually without argument, the identification of gods or abstract concepts.


It is important to add, however, that in making such divine identifications the Derveni author had on the one hand a very congenial poetic text to work on: in column XXII he quotes from the Orphic hymns a line that identifies six different goddesses as a unity, and divine identifications are found frequently in the extant Orphic hymns; [
13] on the other hand, the underlying meaning that he aimed to extract with his reinterpretations was especially well suited to divine identifications, situated as it was in the post-Parmenidean tradition that posits an ultimate unity of existence and, based on Anaxagoras and Diogenes of Apollonia, postulates basic principles like Aer that are the same though they appear under various names. [14]

Interpreter and Text in Pre-Alexandrian Greece

The Derveni Papyrus as Proto-Commentary

And it is also an important characteristic of the Derveni interpreter, at least as I read him, that, for all his cavalier treatment of texts, nevertheless just like Didymus on Demosthenes or other prolific post-Alexandrian interpreters, he would be lost without them: the poem of Orpheus is cited again and again, even in the first six columns he cites Heraclitus, and I still believe it quite possible that in column XI and column XX he cites unnamed prose texts (see the appendix). I also cling to my opinion that, although he clearly uses the technical vocabulary of citation on several occasions for effect, not all citations have to be carefully introduced or their author specified; the principle of seeking parallels and ideas from texts is sufficiently clear that one need never be surprised by a citation around the next corner, and in these cases the scribe has often given us help.

And so, although one can have reservations about the methods and the originality of this writer, nevertheless his voracious reading, intimate familiarity with his text, zest in expounding it, and use of other texts to carry his ideas further, we can agree, all deserve admiration. {126|127}

Appendix: Revisiting the Use of the Paragraphos in P.Derv. X.10–11, XI.8–9, XIII.5–6, XX.10 (Especially), and XXIII.7

I give a structural outline and a translation: [26]

ὅσοι μὲν οὖν] ἀνθρώπω[ν ἐμ] πόλεσιν ἐπιτελέσαντες [τὰ ἱε]ρὰ εἶδον,
Firstly then, those people who have observed the sacred after being publicly initiated
ἔλασσον σφᾶς θαυμάζω μὴ γ[ι]νώσκειν
these I am less surprised that they do not attain knowledge
(οὐ γὰρ οἷόν τε ἀκοῦσαι ὁμοῦ καὶ μαθεῖν τὰ λεγόμενα),
(for it is not possible to hear and learn what is being said at one and the same time); {127|128}
ὅσοι δὲ παρὰ τοῦ τέχνημ ποιουμένου τὰ ἱερὰ (sc. εἶδον),
But those who (have observed the sacred) from an individual craftsman of the sacred
οὗτοι ἄξιοι
They deserve
θαυμάζεσθαι καὶ οἰκτε[ί]ρεσθαι,
both (my) surprise and pity;
θαυμάζεσθαι μὲν ὅτι
Firstly surprise: because
δοκοῦντες  πρότερον ἢ ἐπιτελέσαι εἰδήσειν
although they think they will attain knowledge before they are initiated,
ἀπέρχονται
they end up
ἐπιτελέσαντες πρὶν εἰδέναι
being initiated before they attain knowledge,
οὐδ’ ἑπανερόμενοι
and not asking additional questions either,
ὥσπερ ὡς εἰδότες τ̣[ι]
as if (they did not need to) because they had some knowledge
ὧν εἶδον ἢ ἤκουσαν ἢ ἔμαθον·
of what they have observed and heard and learned
[οἰ]κ̣τε<ί>ρεσθαι δὲ ὅτι
Secondly, pity: because
οὐκ ἀρκε[ῖ] σφιν τὴν δαπάνην προανηλῶσθαι
it is not enough for them to have spent their money in advance,
ἀλλὰ καὶ τῆς γνώμης [
27] στερόμενοι προσαπέρχονται
But they also end up in addition being deprived of their knowledge
(paragraphos) {128|129}
πρὶμ μὲν τὰ [ἱε]ρὰ ἐπιτελέσαι ἐλπίζον̣[τε]ς εἰδήσειν
Although before participating in the sacred things they hope they will attain knowledge
ἐπ̣[ιτελέσ]αν[τες] δὲ στερηθέντες κα̣[ὶ τῆ]ς ἐλπί[δος] ἀπέρχονται.
After participating they end up being deprived of their hope.

Obbink (1997:44–45) attempted to give readers good papyrological grounds to ignore the paragraphos here. I will quote his argument at length in three parts, with my comments interspersed. Initially, he argues that the paragraphos after line 10 could only indicate the beginning of a quotation:

Obbink does not give a list of examples for his claim that a scribe always fills the line at the end of a quotation fully, but I presume he means the like of VIII.3–4, XV.5–6, 10–11 (24, 26, and 19 letter–lines respectively preceding hexameter quotations) as well as the one he cited, XI.7–8 (11 letter–line preceding an unsourced prose quotation); especially lacking, however, is evidence for the claim that a line with 34 as opposed to 38 characters is not “full.” A glance at the photos in KPT shows that many lines are this short without any such external criterion, and a more important factor in line division is obviously that this scribe rarely divides syllables within words between one line and the next (XII.4–5 and XX.6–7 seem to be the only examples). In XX.10 he might have made the line slightly longer by adding πρὶν from the next sentence (as he does with short words e.g. VI.5 [new total 36 characters], XVI.8 [new total 40 characters], XVII.3 [new total 39 characters]), but at XXI.13 he avoids continuing a 34-character line with the available short initial words (ἦν μὲν γ[ὰρ) of a new sentence; at XX.10 there is in addition the factor of another awkward μέν without answering δέ (as at XIII.5–6), so that there are multiple reasons for beginning a new line. The “consistent graphic practice” does not operate here.

But Obbink goes on to cast doubt on the possibility of a quotation of any sort:

Caution, however, must be exercised at this juncture. Though the scribe’s graphic practice appears to be relatively consistent, the use of a paragraphos in school exercises and subliterary texts and even in some ancient critical editions is notoriously irregular, a problem that is compounded by the fact that they are overlooked or inconsistently reported {130|131} by modern editors; the 19th century the delineatores of the Herculaneum papyri, for example, neglected to report them over 50% of the time. In the Derveni papyrus there is at least one irrationally placed paragraphos [XXIII.7], while the paragraphos at XIII.6 may mark nothing more than a strong grammatical clause, as Burkert … notes. I have collated all paragraphoi recorded either in published texts or photographs of the Derveni papyrus. But I’ve not seen the original and am doubtless not aware of them all.

Apart from the difficulty of positing a scribe who is “consistent” at one time and “irrational” at others, the two paragraphoi considered anomalous (XIII.6, XXIII.7) are in fact also strikingly different from their surroundings, both being statements of interpretative method (cited above), quite possibly taken from another context (the first has μέν without answering δέ), but in any case explanatory interruptions in the process of interpretation.

Obbink concludes:

On these grounds I conclude that lines 1–10 of Column XX are not the quoted words of another author, followed by a “feeble prose paraphrase of the last few lines” by the Derveni author. For in this case, we would expect (based on the scribe’s procedure followed elsewhere) line 10 to be filled out by the author’s own remarks we should also be prepared to consider that the paragraphos after line 10 may mark no more than the inception of a grammatical unit. In that case, lines 11 and 12 would represent the author’s rounding out the sentence by reiterating his point in the preceding passage.

While my term “feeble prose paraphrase” was doubtless too harsh for lines 11–12, Obbink’s “rounding out” and “reiterating” seem too generous for them: while lines 1–10 never use the same form twice, every word in lines 11–12 is either a word that has appeared in 1–10 or a gloss on one (πρὶμ glosses πρότερον ἢ ἐπιτελέσαι,. ἐλπίζον̣[τε]ς + future infinitive glosses δ̣οκοῦντες + future infinitive and ἐλπίδος glosses γνώμης (i.e., the expectation of knowledge). Furthermore, these lines, although reproducing (in an anacoluthon) μὲν/ δ̣ὲ from 1–10, lack a sentence connective with what comes before.

Thus even apart from the paragraphos, there are good reasons for assuming a departure from the author’s voice in XX.1–10: the sole first-person verb, sophisticated sentence structure at odds with the commentary form in the section (and with the author’s practice even in cols. I–VI), and, between lines 10 and 11, a lack of explicit sentence-connection combined with total redundancy of contents. {131|132}

Bibliography and Abbreviations

Andrieu, J. 1954. Le dialogue antique: Structure et presentation. Paris.

Bernabé, A., ed. 2004. Poetarum epicorum Graecorum: Testimonia et fragmenta, pars II, fasc. 1: Orphica. Munich.

———. 2004–2005. Poetarum epicorum Graecorum: Testimonia et fragmenta, pars II, fasc. 1–2: Orphicorum et Orphicis similium testimonia et fragmenta. Leipzig.

———. 2007. Poetarum epicorum Graecorum: Testimonia et fragmenta, pars II, fasc. 3: Musaeaus, Linus, Epimenides, Papyrus Derveni, Indices. Leipzig.

Betegh, G. 2002. “Papyrus on the Pyre: The Derveni Papyrus and Its Archaeological Context.” Acta Antiqua Hungarica 42:51–66.

———. 2004. The Derveni Papyrus: Cosmology, Theology, and Interpretation. Cambridge.

Bonfante, L. 2006. “Etruscan Inscriptions and Etruscan Religion.” In The Religion of the Etruscans, ed. N. T. De Grummond and E. Simon, 9–26. Austin.

Bos, A. P. 1989. “A Dreaming Kronos in a Lost Work by Aristotle.” Antiquité classique 58:88–111.

Bottini, A. 1992. Archeologia della salvezza: L’escatologia greca nelle testimonianze archeologiche. Milan.

Burkert, W. 2006a. “Craft versus Sect: The Problem of Orphics and Pythagoreans.” In Kleine Schriften III: Mystica, Orphica, Pythagorica, 190–216. Ed. F. Graf. Göttingen.

———. 2006b. “Der Autor von Derveni: Stesimbrotus Περὶ Τελετῶν?” In Kleine Schriften III: Mystica, Orphica, Pythagorica, 89–94. Ed. F. Graf. Göttingen.

Dorandi, T. 2000. “Le commentaire dans la tradition papyrologique: Quelques cas controversés.” In Le commentaire entre tradition et innovation: Actes du Colloque international de L’institut des traditions textuelles, Paris et Villejuif, 22–25 septembre 1999, ed. M.-O. Goulet-Cazé, 17–27. Paris.

Graf, F. 1974. Eleusis und die orphische Dichtung Athens in vorhellenistischer Zeit. Religionsgeschichtliche Versuche und Vorarbeiten 33. Berlin.

Henrichs, A. 2003. “ ‘Hieroi Logoi’ and ‘Hierai Bibloi’: The (Un)Written Margins of the Sacred in Ancient Greece.” Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 101:207–266.

Irigoin, J. 1984. “Livre et texte dans les manuscrits byzantins de poètes: Conti-nuité et innovations.” In il libro e il testo: atti del convegno internazionale: Urbino, 20–23 settembre 1982, ed. C. Questa and R. Raffaelli, 85–102. Urbino.

Janko, R. 2001. “The Derveni Papyrus (Diagoras of Melos, Apopyrgizontes Logoi?): A New Translation.” Classical Philology 96:1–32.

Johnson, W. A. 1994. “The Function of the Paragraphus in Greek Literary Prose Texts.” Zeitschrift für Papyrologie und Epigraphik 100:65–68.

KPT = Kouremenos, T., G. M. Parássoglou, and G. Tsantsanoglou, eds., The Derveni Papyrus, Edited with a Commentary (Studi e testi per il corpus dei pairi filo-sofici greci e latini 13) (Florence, 2006).

Laks, A. 1997. “Between Religion and Philosophy: The Function of Allegory in the Derveni Papyrus.” Phronesis 42:121–142.

Lamedica, A. 1992. “Il papiro di Derveni come commentario: Problemi formali.” In Proceedings of the XIXth International Congress of Papyrology, Cairo, 2–9 September 1989, ed. E.-M. Abd Alla Hassan, 325–333. Cairo.

Morand, A.-F. 2001. Études sur les hymnes orphiques. Leiden.

Most, G. W. 1985. The Measures of Praise: Structure and Function in Pindar’s Second Pythian and Seventh Nemean Odes. Hypomnemata 83. Göttingen.

———. 1994. “Simonides’ Ode to Scopas in Contexts.” In Modern Critical Theory and Classical Literature, ed. I. J. F. de Jong and J. P. Sullivan, 127–152. Mnemo-syne Suppl. 130. Leiden.

MP3 = Mertens-Pack on Line. P. Mertens and M.-H. Marganne. http://promethee.philo.ulg.ac.be/cedopal/index.htm.

Obbink, D. 1997. “Cosmology as Initiation versus the Critique of the Orphic Mysteries.” In Studies on the Derveni Papyrus, ed. A. Laks and G. W. Most, 39–54. Oxford.

Richardson, N. 1975. “Homeric Professors in the Age of the Sophists.” Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society 21:65–81.

Rusten, J. S. 1985. “Interim Notes on the Papyrus of Derveni.” Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 89:121–140.

Sansone, D. 2004. “Heracles at the Y.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 124:125–142.

Schironi, F. 2001. “L’Olimpo non è il cielo: Esegesi antica nel papiro di Derveni, in Aristarco e in Leagora di Siracusa.” Zeitschrift für Papyrologie und Epigraphik 136:11–21.

Sluiter, I. 1994. “Themistocles, Labeo en de Taalkunde.” Hermeneus 66:210–214.

———. 1997. “The Greek Tradition.” In The Emergence of Semantics in Four Linguistic Traditions: Hebrew, Sanskrit, Greek, Arabic, ed. W. J. v. Bekkum, 149–224. Amsterdam.

Speyer, W. 1970. Bücherfunde in der Glaubenswerbung der Antike, mit einem Ausblick auf Mittelalter und Neuzeit. Hypomnemata 24. Göttingen.

Struck, P. T. 2004. Birth of the Symbol: Ancient Readers at the Limits of Their Texts. Princeton.

Thomas, R. 1993. “Performance and Written Publication in Herodotus and the Sophistic Generation.” In Vermittlung und Tradierung von Wissen in der griechischen Kultur, ed. W. Kullmann and J. Althoff, 225–244. Scriptoralia 61. Tübingen.

Turner, E. G., and P. J. Parsons. 1987. Greek Manuscripts of the Ancient World. University of London Institute of Classical Studies, Bulletin Suppl. 46. London.

Footnotes

[ back ] 1. I am indebted to many at the conference for ideas and corrections (some acknowledged specifically below), but especially to Claude Calame, Albert Henrichs, Sarah Johnston, Franco Montanari, Glenn Most, Dirk Obbink, and Francesca Schironi. Note that in the Greek text cited below I have reproduced the brackets of KPT (for abbreviations see the appended bibliography) but not the dotted letters, which I hope is acceptable, because I do not discuss doubtful readings.

[ back ] 2. See Betegh 2002, and most especially Bottini 1992.

[ back ] 3. I would like to draw attention to a text that might suggest a possible poetic context for cols. III and V as well. In his dialogue On the Face in the Moon (ch. 26 [941F–942B], cf. De defectu oraculorum ch. 18 [420A]), Plutarch makes one character narrate a story he has heard from a stranger of the island of Cronus to the west, beyond Britain. The story is more or less one of a kind, but scholars have frequently pointed to its possible origin as an elaboration of an Orphic theogony-detail: after Zeus overthrows Kronos, he binds him in sleep in a cave, where he is served by daimones who bring him nourishment and are themselves prophetic. But the greatest oracles these daimones bring down to earth are the dreams of Kronos, which foresee what Zeus intends. (Speculations and earlier bibliography in Bos 1989.) [ back ] In the Orphic theogony as well as in the Derveni citations, Zeus receives prophecies not only from night, who is called panompheuousan in col. X, but also Kronos (note thesphata akousas in col. XIII). And Proclus, In Platonis Cratylum commentaria 27 Pasquali = Orph. fr. 239 I–V, also testifies to this double form of divination. We also see that in col. XI the adyton of Night and her oracular powers seem to be interpreted out of existence but to have been present in the poem. Dreams would naturally be the province of Night, as Sarah Johnston reminds me, and so perhaps Plutarch has adapted his myth from an episode in the theogony of Orpheus—many of the right elements are there, though in a different way. [ back ] Against this proposal, it must be conceded that in cols. I–VI (not to speak of col. XX) not only the topic but also the method of discussion seems to be different in form from the rest of the work. Another point against any attempt to relate these early columns to the text of the poem is that col. VII introduces the foundation of the author’s method of interpretation, his assumption that the poem is a riddle, and his quotation of a verse that limits the poem to a select audience.

[ back ] 4. Graf 1974:19. In his contribution to the conference, Graf suggested that the Derveni theogony might in fact be viewed as a cultic hymn (cf. col. V.2) that formed the legomena to an initiation. On Hieroi logoi and Bibloi see Henrichs 2003.

[ back ] 5. That the author is not speaking of poetry in general but of Orpheus in particular is clarified by col. XVIII.2, 6, and the statements of method in cols. XIII.5–6, XXIII.6–7.

[ back ] 6. Albert Henrichs remarked that the supplement ἱερ[ολογεῖ]ται (consulted at the conference, Obbink found no trace of -εῖ-) seems somewhat bold, as it is otherwise first attested late and not in the middle or passive; but the presence of ιερ[ cannot be denied. A more neutral supplement would be μεγάλα ἱερ[ὰ· ἤινικτ]αι.

[ back ] 7. A well-known Orphic verse = Orph. fr. 1ab, 377–378.

[ back ] 8. This paradox is noted by Laks (1997:35).

[ back ] 9. See most recently Sansone 2004:nn5, 56.

[ back ] 10. See Struck 2004:35.

[ back ] 11. There is another soundplay in the fragment of Heraclitus quoted in col. IV, between εὔρους and ἐξευρήσουσι.

[ back ] 12. On the form of argument here see Betegh 2004:250, and for its recurrence in Alexandrian Homer scholarship see Schironi 2001.

[ back ] 13. Morand 2001 “Les rapprochements de dieux,” 156–158, 337–338. I owe this point to Claude Calame.

[ back ] 14. I owe this point to Glenn Most. For the physical system of the Derveni author see Laks 1997:127–134.

[ back ] 15. An accompanying interpretive tactic (XXIV.7, cf. XXVI.11–12) is to hypothesize what the author would have written if the rejected word were his intention: this is applied already by Themistocles in interpreting the Delphic oracle on Salamis (Herodotus 7.141), Sluiter (1994) notes the same method is used for scholarly purposes in the scholia on Iliad 5.408–409, to which P.Derv. can also be added.

[ back ] 16. Francesca Schironi has reminded me of Crates of Mallos especially, who is unusually innovative but still (I would maintain) working within the overall tradition of Homeric scholarship. Franco Montanari reminds me that, true as this is of Alexandrian scholarship, this period is an interpretive parenthesis: both the Presocratics before the Alexandrians and many scholars thereafter (notably the Neoplatonists) used poetry (including Orpheus) as a vehicle for their own philosophical views.

[ back ] 17. Cited in the valuable survey of Sluiter (1997).

[ back ] 18. Most 1994; see also his discussion of the “atomization” of Pindar’s text in the hermeneutic tradition in Most 1985:36–38.

[ back ] 19. See Dorandi 2000 and Lamedica 1992.

[ back ] 20. Irigoin 1984:88, Parsons at Turner and Parsons 1987:151n113, Obbink 1997:44–45n9. I owe this point to Dirk Obbink.

[ back ] 21. Andrieu 1954:263: “Le paragraphos est essentiallement un signe de séparation, et son utilisation dans le dialogue n’est qu’un aspect particulier de ses possibilités.” He discusses its use in the papyri of prose authors 292–297. For Ptolemaic papyrus-commentaries using the paragraphos see MP3 54, 161, 466.

[ back ] 22. Rejected by KPT, Bernabé, the latter paragraphos called “irrational” by Obbink (1997:44) (see below).

[ back ] 23. Treated as colloquial speech rather than a prose quotation by KPT, Bernabé, although elsewhere (XVIII.4, XIX.4–7, XXI.8–9, XXIII.10) the author uses φασί or λέγουσιν or λέγεται κατὰ φάτιν to introduce such colloquial expressions, and in these cases there is no scribal paragraphos, probably because there is no interruption of authorial voice.

[ back ] 24. Obbink 1997:44, on XXIII.7.

[ back ] 25. Already in Burkert 2006b:94n17, Lamedica 1992:328.

[ back ] 26. The commentary on column XX by Kouremenos in KPT 233–242 and by Bernabé (238–241) is especially full, and these, as well as my discussion in Rusten 1985:138–140, are taken for granted below.

[ back ] 27. τῆ̣ς̣ γνώμης στερόμενοι is a variation on μὴ γ[ι]νώσκειν in the first part, closing the ring with the opening idea. This stylistic feature explains what Kouremenos finds “a not particularly successful choice of word” (KPT 241).

[ back ] 28. Here I differ from Graf in his contribution to the conference: he links col. XX with earlier statements to defend the view of the Derveni author as himself a religious entrepreneur (see also Burkert 2006a:202), and asserts that the author’s commentary on the poem offers his answers to the questions the initiate should ask.

[ back ] 29. On first-person argument in the fifth century see Thomas 1993:240–243.

[ back ] 30. Obbink’s initial suggestion that XX.11 is not the end but the start of a quotation would be much strengthened if it were certain that there is a paragraphos after XX.13, as KPT report but Bernabé does not; it is not easy to discern it on the photograph.

[ back ] 31. The ingenious suggestion of Tsantsangolou and Kouremenos (KPT 10, 242) that XX.11–12 is an authorial variant of XX.1–10, as postulated for some passages in Aristotle, has not proved convincing. Johnson (1994) suggested (without reference to P.Derv.) that the paragraphos might serve as a reorientation point for someone reading the text aloud.

[ back ] 32. I suggested (Rusten 1985:140) that the “quotation” might be from the mystery criticism of Diagoras of Melos; Janko (2001), while following Obbink in rejecting it as a quotation, went on to suggest that Diagoras is the author of the entire papyrus.