Use the following persistent identifier: http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:hul.ebook:CHS_Frame.The_Myth_of_Return_in_Early_Greek_Epic.1978.
Notes
Note 1
Note 2
There may also be a latent example in the following lines from the Hymn to Hermes (115–116):
τόφρα δ’ ὑποβρύχιας ἕλικας βοῦς ἕλκε θύραζε.
Elsewhere in Greek (Herodotus, Plato, etc.), the adjective hupobrúkhios always means “underwater.” Particular attention is drawn to the following lines from Homeric Hymn 33, to the Dioscuri, in which distressed sailors call on the two sōtē̂ras … anthrṓpōn … neō̂n te, “saviors of men and ships” (ll. 6–7). The sailors are represented as sacrificing white sheep on the ship’s stern, which the wind and waves have meanwhile “submerged” (11–12): tḕn d’ ánemós te mégas kaì kū̂ma thalássēs / thē̂kan hupobrukhíēn. At this point the Dioscuri come to the rescue. {165|166}
αἶψα μάλ’ ἀνσχεθέειν μεγάλου ὑπὸ κύματος ὁρμῆς.
Note 3
ἀγγελίην πωλεῖται ἐπ’ εὐρέα νῶτα θαλάσσης.
In the case of Calypso, Hermes is the infrequent visitor, as her own greeting to him makes clear (v 87–88):
αἰδοῖός τε φίλος τε; πάρος γε μὲν οὔ τι θαμίζεις.
Both goddesses are reached by crossing the sea; compare Theogony 781, with reference to the rare visits of Iris, with v 50 ff., where Hermes flies across the sea as if he were a bird. Both goddesses live in caves; this is well known in the case of Calypso, and seems to be true of Styx as well—her house is described in Theogony 778 as makrē̂isin pétrēisi katērephé’, “covered over by great rocks.” There is a further, more indirect comparison in the fact that the house of Styx is surrounded by columns which stretch to the sky (Theogony 778–779):
κίσσιν ἀργυρέοισι πρὸς οὐρανὸν ἐστήρικται.
As M. L. West, Hesiod: Theogony (Oxford, 1966), p. 372, has pointed out, Hesiod probably imagines these columns to be at the edge of the world, where the river Styx is said to be connected with the river Oceanus (Theogony 789); West goes on to conjecture that the columns may have something to do with the common notion of pillars which support the sky, and this, I believe, is the case. If so, the columns associated with Styx bring {167|168} to mind the titan Atlas, who also is located at the edge of the world, where he supports the sky (Theogony 517 ff.). This apparent relationship between Styx and Atlas in Hesiod is paralleled by an explicit relationship between Calypso and Atlas in Homer—she is his daughter. One wonders whether it is coincidence that Homer, when he calls Calypso the daughter of Atlas, also mentions the columns of the latter (i 52 ff.):
πάσης βένθεα οἶδεν, ἔχει δέ τε κίονας αὐτὸς
μακράς, αἳ γαῖάν τε καὶ οὐρανὸν ἀμφὶς ἔχουσι.
Note 4
ναίετ’ ἐπ’ Εὐρώτᾳ καλλιρόῳ ποταμῷ,
εἴ ποτε βουλεύσαιμι φίλῳ κακόν, αὐτὸς ἔχοιμι·
εἰ δέ τι κεῖνος ἐμοί, δὶς τόσον αὐτὸς ἔχοι.
When twins abandon one another, on the other hand, they do so out of hostility; see Ward, The Divine Twins (chap. 6, n. 36), pp. 6–7, who cites the examples of the biblical Jacob and Esau, the Greek Acrisius and Proetus, and the Roman Romulus and Remus. Now the little that is known about Nā̊ŋhaiθya characterizes him precisely as a cause of hostility between superiors and inferiors. According to the Persian source which is translated by E. E. K. Antia, Cama Memorial Volume (Bombay, 1900), p. 163, and is also quoted by G. Dumézil, Naissance d’archanges (Paris, 1945), p. 167, Nā̊ŋhaiθya creates discord between men and God, parents and children, teachers and pupils, husbands and wives, masters and servants. This demonic function may well derive from a tradition that Nā̊ŋhaiθya quarreled with and abandoned his twin brother.
Note 5
and by a similar line in the account of himself which Odysseus gives to Penelope (xxiii 253):
A fascinating parallel is that between Odysseus’s command to his steersman to “ward off the ship” from both Scylla and Charybdis (éerge nē̂a in xii 219–220) and Parmenides’ admonition in Frag. 6.3–4:
αὐτὰρ ἔπειτ’ ἀπὸ τῆς …
and his command in Frag. 7.2–3:
μηδέ σ’ ἔθος πολύπειρον ὁδὸν κατὰ τήνδε βιάσθω …
Havelock nicely comments (p. 138) that “the object to be controlled is no longer a ship but a mental process,” and draws attention to Frag. 6.5–6, where there is a more concrete instance of the ship metaphor:
στήθεσιν ἰθύνει πλακτὸν νόον· οἱ δὲ φοροῦνται …
as “the gates of the paths of day and night.” The author has inadvertently translated Parmenides, Frag. 1.11:
and has thus overlooked the crucial difference between the two lines in question. I have argued earlier that Parmenides, far from being the imitator in this case, has preserved the genuine form of a line which Homer has modified (see above chap. 3, text at n. 42). I have further tried to show that Hesiod, in the Theogony, was dealing independently with the same mythic material as Homer and Parmenides (see above chap. 3, text at nn. 43–45); this at once suggests that more is involved in Parmenides than particular literary reminiscences.
and the foolish companions of Odysseus, as well as the ghosts in Hades whom these companions soon join. But the notion of an “amorphous mass of common men” from whom an “elite” is distinguished is basic both to the Odyssey and to the development of a philosophic tradition; and in both cases, as I have argued earlier, sun mythology seems largely responsible for this notion (see chap. 2, text at nn. 19–23 on the Odyssey and chap. 2, text at nn. 30–32 on the Greek philosophic tradition). Given this, I cannot believe with Havelock (p. 140) that Parmenides, in conceiving of his Hēliádes, has seized upon the daughters of Helios who guard their father’s cattle in the Odyssey, and “converted (them) from herdsmen into outriders.” The entire situation in Parmenides’ proem speaks too strongly for the independent influence of sun mythology.
οὐδέ ποτε φθινύθουσι
and suggests that this detail, more than anything else, led Parmenides to “link the daughters of the sun with the marvels of a mental journey which had taken the traveler into an absolute, where there is no coming to be and no passing away”; the author here refers to the cornerstone of Paremenides’ thought, which is articulated in Frag. 8.21 by the words:
Once again Havelock’s observation seems to me to be full of insight, but once again I prefer to reverse the argument. Is it {173|174} because Parmenides’ thought excludes “coming to be” and “passing away” that he introduces, by way of literary reminiscence, the daughters of the sun? Or is it, rather, that the tradition of sun mythology has influenced his thought? In Parmenides’ realm of Truth, there is only Being; Non-Being is impossible, and “perishing is unimaginable” (ápustos ólethros). Only in the realm of Opinion does there seem to be such a thing as Non-Being. I suggest that these distinctions are very similar to those with which the primitive root nes– is involved. In the line:
common men are lost (compare olésantes with ólethros in Parmenides), but the elite “return from death;” in other words, are immortal. Does the root nes– (“return from death”) not erase the distinction between Being and Non-Being, and in so doing stand in opposition to “destruction”? The history of this root, it seems to me, should be taken into account in attempting to understand the thought of a philosopher who, by his possession of nóos and his awareness that Non-Being does not exist, considers himself to be elite, and who relegates the idea of “destruction” to the “tribes uncounted and uncritical.”